Skip to main content

Thank you for visiting nature.com. You are using a browser version with limited support for CSS. To obtain the best experience, we recommend you use a more up to date browser (or turn off compatibility mode in Internet Explorer). In the meantime, to ensure continued support, we are displaying the site without styles and JavaScript.

  • Article
  • Published:

Bayesianism and wishful thinking are compatible

An Author Correction to this article was published on 02 April 2024

This article has been updated

Abstract

Bayesian principles show up across many domains of human cognition, but wishful thinking—where beliefs are updated in the direction of desired outcomes rather than what the evidence implies—seems to threaten the universality of Bayesian approaches to the mind. In this Article, we show that Bayesian optimality and wishful thinking are, despite first appearances, compatible. The setting of opposing goals can cause two groups of people with identical prior beliefs to reach opposite conclusions about the same evidence through fully Bayesian calculations. We show that this is possible because, when people set goals, they receive privileged information in the form of affective experiences, and this information systematically supports goal-consistent conclusions. We ground this idea in a formal, Bayesian model in which affective prediction errors drive wishful thinking. We obtain empirical support for our model across five studies.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution

Access options

Buy this article

Prices may be subject to local taxes which are calculated during checkout

Fig. 1: Predicted versus observed affect as a function of case and whether participants were incentivized to defend the plaintiff’s position (pro-plaintiff) or the defendant’s position (pro-defendant) in study 1.
Fig. 2: The results of studies 2 and 3.
Fig. 3: The results of study 4.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

The data that support the findings of this study are available at https://osf.io/59dmr/?view_only=b8ea1a66b5e84d1e8d67391662b60d82.

Code availability

The custom code that supports the findings of this study is available at https://osf.io/59dmr/?view_only=b8ea1a66b5e84d1e8d67391662b60d82.

Change history

References

  1. Knill, D. C. & Pouget, A. The Bayesian brain: the role of uncertainty in neural coding and computation. Trends Neurosci. 27, 712–719 (2004).

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  2. Doya, K., Ishii, S., Pouget, A. & Rao, R. P. Bayesian Brain: Probabilistic Approaches to Neural Coding (MIT, 2007).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Hohwy, J. The Predictive Mind (Oxford Univ. Press, 2013).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Clark, A. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 36, 181–204 (2013).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  5. Lee, T. S. & Mumford, D. Hierarchical Bayesian inference in the visual cortex. J. Opt. Soc. Am. A Opt. Image Sci. Vis. 20, 1434–1448 (2003).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Oaksford, M. & Chater, N. Bayesian Rationality: The Probabilistic Approach to Human Reasoning (Oxford Univ. Press, 2007).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Friston, K. The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory? Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 11, 127–138 (2010).

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  8. Tenenbaum, J. B., Kemp, C., Griffiths, T. L. & Goodman, N. D. How to grow a mind: statistics, structure, and abstraction. Science 331, 1279–1285 (2011).

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  9. Barrett, L. F. The theory of constructed emotion: an active inference account of interoception and categorization. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 12, 1–23 (2017).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  10. Williams, D. Hierarchical Bayesian models of delusion. Conscious. Cogn. 61, 129–147 (2018).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  11. Tappin, B. M. & Gadsby, S. Biased belief in the Bayesian brain: a deeper look at the evidence. Conscious. Cogn. 68, 107–114 (2019).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Mandelbaum, E. Troubles with Bayesianism: an introduction to the psychological immune system. Mind Lang. 34, 141–157 (2019).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Lord, C. G., Ross, L. & Lepper, M. R. Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: the effects of prior theories on subsequently considered evidence. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 37, 2098–2109 (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Madson, G. J. & Hillygus, D. S. All the best polls agree with me: bias in evaluations of political polling. Political Behav. 42, 1055–1072 (2020).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Kunda, Z. The case for motivated reasoning. Psychol. Bull. 108, 480–498 (1990).

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  16. Druckman, J. N. & McGrath, M. C. The evidence for motivated reasoning in climate change preference formation. Nat. Clim. Change 9, 111–119 (2019).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Kahan, D. M. in Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences (eds Scott, R. A. et al.) 1–15 (John Wiley & Sons, 2015).

  18. Gershman, S. J. How to never be wrong. Psychon. Bull. Rev. 26, 13–28 (2019).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  19. Jern, A., Chang, K.-M. K. & Kemp, C. Belief polarization is not always irrational. Psychol. Rev. 121, 206–224 (2014).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  20. Cook, J. & Lewandowsky, S. Rational irrationality: modeling climate change belief polarization using Bayesian networks. Top. Cogn. Sci. 8, 160–179 (2016).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  21. Neuman, R., Rafferty, A. & Griffiths, T. A bounded rationality account of wishful thinking. In Proc. Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society Vol. 36 (Cognitive Science Society, 2014).

  22. Dorst, K. Rational polarization. Philos. Rev. 132, 355–458 (2023).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Melnikoff, D. E. & Strohminger, N. The automatic influence of advocacy on lawyers and novices. Nat. Hum. Behav. 4, 1258–1264 (2020).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  24. Batson, C. D. Rational processing or rationalization? The effect of disconfirming information on a stated religious belief. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 32, 176–184 (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Caplin, A. & Leahy, J. V. Wishful Thinking Working Paper No. w25707 (National Bureau of Economic Research, 2019).

  26. Loewenstein, G. & Lerner, J. S. in Handbook of Affective Sciences (eds Davidson, R. J. et al.) 619–642 (Oxford Univ. Press, 2003).

  27. Schwarz, N. & Clore, G. L. Mood as information: 20 years later. Psychol. Inq. 14, 296–303 (2003).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Clore, G. L. & Huntsinger, J. R. How emotions inform judgment and regulate thought. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11, 393–399 (2007).

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  29. Heffner, J., Son, J.-Y. & FeldmanHall, O. Emotion prediction errors guide socially adaptive behaviour. Nat. Hum. Behav. 5, 1391–1401 (2021).

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  30. Barrett, L. F. & Simmons, W. K. Interoceptive predictions in the brain. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 16, 419–429 (2015).

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  31. Seth, A. K. & Friston, K. J. Active interoceptive inference and the emotional brain. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B 371, 20160007 (2016).

    Google Scholar 

  32. Atzil, S., Gao, W., Fradkin, I. & Barrett, L. F. Growing a social brain. Nat. Hum. Behav. 2, 624–636 (2018).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  33. Hoemann, K., Xu, F. & Barrett, L. F. Emotion words, emotion concepts, and emotional development in children: a constructionist hypothesis. Dev. Psychol. 55, 1830–1849 (2019).

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  34. Mathys, C. D. et al. Uncertainty in perception and the hierarchical Gaussian filter. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 8, 825 (2014).

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  35. Gershman, S. J. A unifying probabilistic view of associative learning. PLoS Comput. Biol. 11, e1004567 (2015).

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  36. Festinger, L. & Carlsmith, J. M. Cognitive consequences of forced compliance. J. Abnorm. Psychol. 58, 203–210 (1959).

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  37. Bem, D. J. Self-perception: an alternative interpretation of cognitive dissonance phenomena. Psychol. Rev. 74, 183–200 (1967).

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  38. Robinson, M. J. & Berridge, K. C. Instant transformation of learned repulsion into motivational ‘wanting’. Curr. Biol. 23, 282–289 (2013).

  39. Dayan, P. & Berridge, K. C. Model-based and model-free Pavlovian reward learning: revaluation, revision, and revelation. Cogn. Affect. Behav. Neurosci. 14, 473–492 (2014).

    PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  40. Melnikoff, D. E. & Bailey, A. H. Preferences for moral vs. immoral traits in others are conditional. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 115, E592–E600 (2018).

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  41. Melnikoff, D. E., Lambert, R. & Bargh, J. A. Attitudes as prepared reflexes. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 88, 103950 (2020).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Loewenstein, G. Out of control: visceral influences on behavior. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 65, 272–292 (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Loewenstein, G., O’Donoghue, T. & Rabin, M. Projection bias in predicting future utility. Q. J. Econ. 118, 1209–1248 (2003).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Read, D. & Van Leeuwen, B. Predicting hunger: the effects of appetite and delay on choice. Organ. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 76, 189–205 (1998).

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  45. Rescorla, R. A. & Wagner, A. R. in Classical Conditioning II: Current Research and Theory (eds Black, A. H. & Prokasy, W. F.) 64–99 (Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1972).

  46. Bush, R. R. & Mosteller, F. Stochastic Models for Learning (Wiley, 1955).

    Google Scholar 

  47. Sutton, R. S. Learning to predict by the methods of temporal differences. Mach. Learn. 3, 9–44 (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  48. Festinger, L. A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance (Stanford Univ. Press, 1957).

    Google Scholar 

  49. Elliot, A. J. & Devine, P. G. On the motivational nature of cognitive dissonance: dissonance as psychological discomfort. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 67, 382–394 (1994).

    Google Scholar 

  50. Seth, A. K. Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self. Trends Cogn. Sci. 17, 565–573 (2013).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  51. Smith, R. et al. A Bayesian computational model reveals a failure to adapt interoceptive precision estimates across depression, anxiety, eating, and substance use disorders. PLoS Comput. Biol. 16, e1008484 (2020).

    CAS  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  52. Mercier, H. & Sperber, D. Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behav. Brain Sci. 34, 57–74 (2011).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  53. von Hippel, W. & Trivers, R. The evolution and psychology of self-deception. Behav. Brain Sci. 34, 1–16 (2011).

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

D.E.M. was supported by the Stanford Graduate School of Business. N.S. was supported by the Wolpow Family Faculty Scholar Fund, the Wharton Dean’s Research Fund and the Wharton Behavioral Lab. The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish or preparation of the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

D.E.M. and N.S. jointly designed the studies, analysed the data and wrote the paper. D.E.M. is responsible for the formal model; in an equally weighty intellectual achievement, N.S. is responsible for typesetting that model in LaTeX.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David E. Melnikoff.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The authors declare no competing interests.

Peer review

Peer review information

Nature Human Behaviour thanks Adam Bear, Mike Oaksford and the other, anonymous, reviewer(s) for their contribution to the peer review of this work. Peer reviewer reports are available.

Additional information

Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Supplementary information

Supplementary Information

Supplementary Methods, Results, Figs. 1 and 2 and References.

Reporting Summary

Peer Review File

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Melnikoff, D.E., Strohminger, N. Bayesianism and wishful thinking are compatible. Nat Hum Behav 8, 692–701 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-024-01819-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-024-01819-6

This article is cited by

Search

Quick links

Nature Briefing

Sign up for the Nature Briefing newsletter — what matters in science, free to your inbox daily.

Get the most important science stories of the day, free in your inbox. Sign up for Nature Briefing