Introduction

We are in a time of crisis: the emergence of pandemic agents, loss of biodiversity, climate change, geopolitical conflicts, etc. Recently, the COVID-19 pandemic and the resurgence of a form of Cold War spread large in international discussions (Valdés and Rendtorff, 2021; Diaz-Castro et al., 2023). Those raise several concerns on Health (see the Manhattan 2004 to Berlin 2019 Principles), Climate (see the 2022 Conference of Parties 27 in Egypt) and Biodiversity (see the 2022 COP15 in Kunming-Montreal). Moreover, these concerns complexify and intensify when intertwined with Technology (see the Joint Partnership on Artificial Intelligence) and the Economy (the 2022 Group 20 in Indonesia). For the biologist Van Rensselaer Potter (1911–2001), the one who coined the term ‘bioethics’ between 1964 and 1971 (Potter, 1971), this ‘global’ crisis is ongoing since the beginning of humanity, as humans must adapt, even learn and equip themselves, to survive (Potter, 1988)Footnote 1. However, since the last century, Western scholars have realized environmental crises deserve our attention: the environment affects our—as individuals—state of health and our—as Society—vision of the future (Potter, 1971). To do so, we must increase the awareness of the surrounding space (our environment, context and standpoint), as set in the Canadian Journal of Bioethics in terms of ecological (e.g., biology, geology, and chemistry), social (e.g., politics, economics, and culture), and intellectual (e.g., literature, education, and critical thinking) environment (Boudreau LeBlanc, 2023)Footnote 2. Juggling this ‘environmental’ polysemy can quickly become complicated, even becoming a slippery slope leading to the oblivion of protecting wildlife and social services for building ever-more (infra)structuresFootnote 3. Nonetheless, being aware of the environment does not mean transforming the surrounding milieus into a humanly attractive (i.e., useful, productive. aesthetic, etc.) order, as already coined by Aldo Leopold (1887–1948; Potter, 1988; Boudreau LeBlanc, 2023) early in the 20th century on the control over the land (stewardship) vs the cooperation within/with the land (Potter, 1988; Leopold, 1949).

At first glance, ecological, social, and intellectual environments seem unconnected or unconnectable. But the Philosophy of Science identifies a subtle relationship (an interdependence)Footnote 4. Due to the cognitive and behaviors, individuals are capable of social changes and then scaling an idea emerging from their mind (the intellectual organization) up to a collective set of actors (the social organization) and systematically act on their surroundings, which over time will transform their biotic community (the ecological organization) (Boudreau LeBlanc, 2023). However, to organizationally scaled up an idea, one individual has to envision an engaging future (i.e., having a vision) to enrol peers in the effort for collective change (i.e., for leadership, (Roger, 2003). According to Potter, these willing individuals are engaged scientists, concerned citizens, and—fundamentally—‘fieldwork bioethicists’Footnote 5. In this argument, we use the ecosystemic approach to highlight this interdependence (Dawes et al., 2016; Jonak et al., 2016)Footnote 6 and explore ways to manage the (epistemological) risk of interdisciplinary translation. For instance, the political overuse of ‘ecosystem’ tends to reduce the theoretical basis of ecology (a natural science) to a social (even activist) position strictly concerned with non-human beings and things (Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2021a; Zhu, 2012). Consequently, it is challenging to recognize social and political issues as embedded in the ecological environmentFootnote 7. Accordingly, the term ‘ecosystemic’, popularized by the Earth Summits (see the United Nations UN, 1992), has radiated in several sectors without fully acknowledging the strong interdependence between, among others, ecology, management (Epstein, 2016) and health (Forget and Lebel, 2001). This approach is promoted in the literature on Sustainability and aims, at first glance, to reconcile environmental, financial and cultural interests. Henceforth, a minor link remains between the ‘ecosystemic’ approach (a metaphor) and physical ecosystems (a model), which can be a strength (Pickett and Cadenasso, 2002), but a slippery slope at the same time (Wylie, 1982).

According to Wahl-Jorgensen (2016), the ecosystemic approach relates to Chicago School history, known for its application of the ecological model in criminology. Studying digital environments, Jonak et al. (2016) sophisticate the metaphor to understand the social processes, scales and (macro) organization of Science, Technology & Society using the Darwinian conceptual framework (adaptability, evolution, plasticity, community, etc.). In Philosophy of Sustainability, Norton (2005) reminds Charles Darwin’s (1809–1882; Darwin, 1859) call for a new field of study: the ‘Economy of Nature’, coined later as ‘Ecology’Footnote 8. Suppose these metaphorical relationships are creatively constructive, as Thomas Malthus (1766–1834)’s model inspired Darwin to explain the (ecological) population’s exponential growth. But they can become a slippery slope leading to injustice, as the reductive Malthusian (social) conclusion of having a birth control policy, which applies to the impoverished of society to control population growthFootnote 9.

This paper argues for deepening the epistemology of the ecosystemic approach to bridge the Medical & Environmental fields (studies, sectors, and technics) in an integrated management practice of Care, Production & Biodiversity. To address this radical (epistemological) gap, the argument navigates through the History of Ecology & Sociology before deepening its Philosophy or Science foundation in light of the Potterian and Leopoldian views on the Biology & Ethics bridging values. These two authors are pioneers of new techniques, including the community-based adaptive ecosystem(ic) management (or co-management) approach (Norton, 2005), and open a new path for operationalizing Global Bioethics.

Theoretical hybridization

Ecology has inspired and been enriched by many fields of knowledgeFootnote 10. For instance, the Chicago School emerges in sociology at the time Arthur Tansley (1871–1955, 1935), who coins the term ‘ecosystem’ in plant ecology. Accordingly, the two distinctive perspectives have co-evolved on the topic of ‘urban ecology’ since then. The Baltimore School, introduced by Steward Pickett et al. (1985; 2011), formalizes ecosystem ecology in urban studies. Pickett’s ecological view is mathematical; it focuses on the phenomenon of biogeochemical cycles and the biochemical mechanisms of thermodynamics (Pickett and Cadenasso, 2002; Pickett and Grove, 2009). Conversely, the ecological view of the Chicago School is socio-political. It focuses on sociology, notably the system of discourses and power dynamics, and more precisely on groups embedded in a psychological, economic and cultural context (e.g., factors of influence). While attempts to reconcile these three perspectives of Urban Ecology are underway (Jonak et al., 2016; Wahl-Jorgensen, 2016; Rademacher et al., 2019; Stone-Jovicich, 2015; Dwiartama and Rosin, 2014; Lave, 2015), a critical work remains to orient this translation, dialogue, and—to some extent—theoretical learning and interdisciplinary hybridization. And it is at this stage of the reflection that bioethics became relevant to open the dialogue on uncertainties and prevent the risk of disciplinary reductionism (Callahan, 1973); sometimes caused by institutional conflicts of interests (Olivier and Williams-Jones, 2014) and (intellectual) power dynamics from hegemonical over more silent disciplines (Beever and Morar, 2019); other times caused by a misunderstanding of the scope and reasoning of the discipline of our colleagues, for instance, oncology and ethics (Potter, 1971), wildlife management and ethics (Potter, 1988), medicine and ecology (Beever and Morar, 2019), medicine and philosophy (Ferrarello, 2023). Framing these interdisciplinary translations is essential to ensure technical advances without introducing confusion in each fieldFootnote 11. All three have distinct criteria to value knowledge (e.g., axiological and epistemological) and must operate interdependently (or co-operate). Each field prioritizes different paths to learning and access to knowledge differently due to its respective value, which pulses its meaning, purpose, and senseFootnote 12.

The ecosystemic approach involves system thinking. The logic of system thinking is part of the Complex Theory philosophy. It means making sense of the world through element networks (relationships) and organizational functioning (phenomena), instead of the elementary study of the parts or the whole. Under this perspective, intervention is no longer a punctual action conducted on a targeted issue for a particular end (i.e., a linear problem-solving logic). Consequently, health and environment interventions must pursue a more adaptive, learning, and reflexive reasoning. Elinor Ostrom (1933–2012) explains human systems through collective norms (2000), which go beyond interpersonal relationships and includes intergenerational learnings (Henrich and Muthukrishna, 2023) and a human interspecies sense of responsibility (ten Have, 2011). In the same line of thought, the sociological model of Ernest Burgess (1886–1966, see Swannack and Grant, 2008)—later used by Eugene Odum (1913–2002) in ecosystem ecologyFootnote 13—is helpful to unpack the meaning of systems, of collectives and of communities (see Leopold on the ‘biotic community’, Dawes et al., 2016; Wylie, 1982; Wahl-Jorgensen, 2016). Burgess and Odum organize concentrically knowledge: the system (a meso-structure) embeds individuals; the cognitive (micro) is nested in a large set of collective-network (the system); while all interact organizationally (macro) with the environment. Bruno Latour (1947–2022) uses an analogous knowledge architecture in sociology. His theory on actors, networks, and translation advances this perspective on complexity – even unpacks its application on the social (Latour, 2007; Bilodeau and Potvin, 2018; De Munck, 2017). Henceforth, Anne Rademacher et al. (2015). highlight the need for methodological bridges in the practice milieus: “The work of assembling robust ethnographic and clearly historicized portraits of urban socio-natural transformation, and of reaching beyond the laboratory […] is notably scarce”. To ease this bridging process, we need methods to materialize the (macro-organizational) ‘dialogue’ among scholars and, historically, between societies, generations, and (abstractly) lands. We need a ‘translation process’ (Callon et al., 2001), even a ‘hybrid forum’ or ‘hybrid community’, as coined by Michel Callon (see Appendix 1; 2004),Footnote 14 or a multispecies ethnography, as outlined by Rademacher et al. (2019), to building a shared sense (i.e., values) of a better future (Potter, 1971) from the in situ experience of experts and local inhabitants. Consistent with his iconic prose, Leopold calls for a method that Sketches here and there to contextualize interventions within their milieu and for their inhabitants: he calls for a collective communitarian ethics that he labels The Land Ethic (1949).

Values and sciences are inseparable in dealing with the uncertainty surrounding complex knowledge and decisions (Metzger and Salmond, 2008; Douglas, 2007; Funtowicz and Ravetz, 2008; Norton, 2008). Dominique Charron, who advanced the ecosystem approach to human health (ecohealth), reminds us: “Ethical dilemmas should be expected by [and studied by] researchers who anticipate them and take them into account in advance are sometimes better prepared to deal with them” (2014). Edgar Morin and scholars in bioethics (1992; de Langavant, 2001; Wilson, 2014; Maldonado and Garzón, 2022; Chursinova et al., 2022) use the complexity perspective in Philosophy or Science to reframe multilemmas opposing individuals with the collective. Ethics is about values; it refers to the studies of its reasoning, its distributions in Society, and its use by people to deal with complicated choices (dilemmas) (Potter, 1972). This new way of doing, where sciences and values are intertwined, echoes (Funtowicz and Ravetz, 1993) philosophy of Post-Normal Sciences. This philosophy builds on the elementary work of Thomas Kuhn (1922–1996) on the Structure of the Evolution of [Normal] Sciences (1962). Funtowicz and Ravetz advance a new logic for in-action and in-situ sciences—when knowledge makes its “entrance into society”. Kuhn’s ‘normal’ disciplines point to the kind of sciences that is conducted inside the ‘laboratory’ (see also Potter, 1964). Adding ethics in situ of science functioning is arguably the missing piece to advance knowledge outside the laboratoryFootnote 15.

Charron poses some limits to in-action sciences, as coined by Latour (1987): “Research may not be the way to bring about the changes that communities expect” and this requires a necessary resignation of researchers about their interest and goal: “which is, of course, not desirable for any project” (Charron, 2014). Thus, the in-action requires discipline (literally) and framing the conduct of researchers and responsible innovation in sciences. Research techniques must innovate to be helpful to the community. However, constructing knowledge with communities, known as co-construction, adds epistemological complexity. As Peter and Catherine Whitehouse (2020) suggested, Post-Normal Sciences, Transdisciplinary Perspective, and Action-Research Methodologies make sense (epistemologically) in light of the Potterian view of bioethics. In-action sciences and ethics require documentation, monitoring, and a (multisite) management process conducted at local scales—thus acknowledging specific challenges—but guide in light of general knowledge to foresee more globally (Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2022a). Science, not only research, should evolve through experimentalism, which means investing in the governance of innovation, managing the trajectory of discoveries and prioritizing scientific quests—practical and technological as well as applied and fundamental—by adaptive logic based on bioethical discussions. Science must open up to “a wider range of strategies that go beyond communities to influence the system where deeper and longer-term change is possible” (Charron, 2014). But which Council on the Future must guide the way?

Building awareness of the context

Under the term ‘bioethics’, Potter advances the philosophy of Leopold. Indeed, bioethics must be “buil[t] on the Legacy of Leopold”. Although Potter has focused his scientific work on oncology and his ethical reflections on policies and technologies, their conceptual framework converges through biological, even ecological metaphors. They argue for bridging the social and ecological dimensions in a global system contextualizing the daily life of individuals and the communityFootnote 16.

Figure 1 introduces some concepts of Leopold’s theoretical framework on the biotic community and ecological landscapesFootnote 17. Some scholars outline that the thesis of Potter is “the story of a lost battle” (Potter, 2011; Durand, 2005), but we disagree here. The battle—we should emphasize the intellectual debate on complexity (de Langavant, 2001; Wilson, 2014; Maldonado and Garzón, 2022)—starts way before Leopold, transcends its biography, and even Potter’s work. And the story is about applying pragmatism in ethics (Norton, 2005; ten Have, 2012) and the Philosophy of complexity to Society, starting with medical and environmental practices. Hence, Potter does not conceive bioethics as a new “topic” of study (Durand, 2005): an ethics applied to health, life (bio-) and the environment. Instead, he conceives bioethics as a new set of “post-normal science” methodologies and pathways.

Fig. 1: The Global Hybrid Theory of Bio-Ethics.
figure 1

The idea of a Global Bioethics is, for Potter (2011), the socio-intellectual organization that is encompassing the applied sciences (the 'Bio') and applied ethics that is focusing on one element (the individual, population, species, etc.) or its surrounding system/habitat (e.g., environment). The conceptualization of such organization starts by a Hybrid Theory between two types of (sub) Bioethics, such as the (bio) medical and ecological ones (an adaptation of the 4th chapter, ‘Two Kinds of Bioethics’ in ‘Global Bioethics’, hybridizing theories from two cultures: biology and ethics)Footnote

This figure is adapted from Van Rensselaer Potter’s (1911–2001) 1988 book on “Global Bioethics: Building on the Legacy of [Aldo] Leopold” (1887–1948). To update Potter’s thinking, certain liberties have been taken. One of the main criticisms of Potter’s arguments is about ‘controlling human fertility’ and‘ stabilizing the world population’. These formulations certainly appear radical to people outside the jargon of ecology. To facilitate translation of the perspective, the figure makes explicit the perspective, a priori general (applied to all species): ‘Management of population dynamics and behaviors’ and ‘Responsible governance of human actions, dynamics and organization’. If a ‘political’ control of fertility proceeds with intrusive regulations into private life which literally limit births, an ecological understanding implies increasing education, parental care, resources allocated to women, etc., to increase care per child (strategy K) instead of increasing the frequency of births with low ‘parentalité’ and social care (strategy R). While the political understanding of ‘fertility control’ is short-term and with interventionist measures, the ecological understanding is long-term and with organizational resilience.

.

Potter 1988 schematization aims at identifying the pathway (arrows) to operate global bioethics. Conceptually, Potter frames bioethics in terms of a ‘Global’ (Potter and Lisa, 2001) ‘Acceptable’ (Potter, 1992) ‘Survival’ in light of the individuals, their society (human), the (biotic) community, and the Land (Fig. 1). Bioethics must operate, he explained, as a ‘Council on the Future’ (Hottois, 2011)Footnote 19. In 1964, he emphasized the function of Sciences as a powerful way to inform Policy. Not only a set of knowledge, Science appears to him as a social collective of experts, measures, surveys, criteria, concepts, theories, etc., while Policy is a social collective of persons, artefacts and laws with their own concepts and theories; and both collective are made of cultures, believes, controversies, etc. Still, he acknowledged that Science alone cannot (globally) be that Council (Potter, 1971). Indeed, at the limit of the factual ‘certainties’ of Science, values must guide human decisions and their systematization into norms (e.g., a policy, law, economy, technology, etc.). And beyond the power of facts and values, norms influence human behavior and societal views on the future. For Potter, a Global Council is a kind of (figuratively) System Thinking unit aiming to articulate these three components of the choice architecture: fact, value, and norm (as a ‘Thinking like a mountain’, like an inhabitant, and like a professional to recall Leopold poetic proseFootnote 20, Fig. 1; Max-Neef, 2005; Stoeklé et al., 2020). Furthermore, the task of the Council is not metaphysical, but profoundly empirical and action-oriented, helping individuals to make Cornelian choices and orienting institutional governance bodies to systematize decision-making, policies and regimes adequately. The Council’s advice is given on the basis of a global thinking to support local ethical prioritizations (resource allocation, perspective plurality, power dynamics, etc.). For Potter, this System Thinking Council is a kind of a science-based ethics at the interface of knowledge, technologies and practices that gives the right ‘social environment’ and adaptive agility to evolve quickly on a local scale without losing sight of the (let’s say, Kuhnian and Leopoldian) bigger picture (Fig. 1)Footnote 21.

For Potter, envisioning the future is valuated in terms of acceptability. An acceptable project should sur·vive (literally in addition to life) up to the ‘third millennium’ while considering local vulnerabilities (Potter and Lisa, 2001; Potter, 1990; Potter and Whitehouse, 1998). Consequently, acceptability is not (strictly) about consensus and norms, which would be a slippery slope toward the sacralization of the Power of the Majority and the Rule of Law, and will not survive the vivid test of the enduring (millennium) realityFootnote 22. Acceptability is about values and responsibility. Considering the Jonasian Principle of Responsibility, acceptability places the burden of social-environmental duties on the shoulder of those (persons or institutions) who hold the power. We should avoid the fallacy of sharing responsibilities among the poorest (without the resources or skills) to handle specific / specialized operations for the sake of democracy. The Potterian acceptability helps to conceive and provide paths towards operationalising a more communitarian perspective. As a result, the responsibility is more equitably shared. Moreover, those in positions of power are then more systematically held accountable for their actions if the regime is, by design, iteratively evaluative (reflexive and adaptive) in light of collective values through cyclical community dynamics (Diaz-Castro et al., 2023; Emerson and Gerlak, 2014; Kemp and Loorbach, 2006; Loorbach et al., 2016; Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2022b). Thus, the acceptable risk / benefit estimation is not projected by a third party outside the community. The estimate is defined ongoingly by / for the community negotiating local-specific and global-generic governance attributes and qualities for responsibility (Fig. 1).

In practice, acceptability is a set of common—but evolving—criteria characterizing principles of conduct. Each principle opens the dialogue about viable action paths in daily life and for sustainability. In a nod to Potter, let’s call this wisdom a communitarian ‘collective bioethics’, which outlines the responsible actor (the human). Alternatively, if we mobilize the Leopoldian philosophy, the label focus on the scope: building ‘The Land Ethic’, which outlines the responsibility towards the shared resources, habitat, history, and context (Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2022b): this perspective adds to Potter’s 1971 explanation the globality of an ecosystem ‘social bioethics’ dimension. However, we argue that both labels are two sides of the same coin. Under the vocabulary of Ostrom, those ethics pose criteria and paths that pulse a ‘self-organized collective action’ aiming for a ‘long-surviving’ in regards to the ‘commonly shared resource regimes’ (2000). Regarding the regime, human systems have the capacity of self-organization through communication, collaboration, and education (Loorbach, 2007; Schoon and Van Der Leeuw, 2015; Kovacic, 2017), but face the challenge of knowledge translation and dissemination to inform decisions as a result of inter-cultural, inter-disciplinary, inter-generational, even inter-species dialogue: let’s say a ‘theoretical hybridization’, a ‘working theory’ or, as coined by Alison Wylie in the field of archaeology, an “unifying strategies of a more local and contingent nature” (1999, p.1). Figure 1 hybridizes the organizational and temporal dimensions from the people’s short-term perspective up to the community’s long-term one.

  1. 1.

    Hybridizing organizational Sociology & Ecology, acknowledging individuals as elements with cognitive & behaviors capable of interacting with counterparts & the environment—the complex & adaptive system.

  2. 2.

    Hybridizing the physical & political dimensions of organizations, acknowledging interactions influenced by encompassing ones—the scale phenomenon & fractality principle.

  3. 3.

    Hybridizing the Anthropology & Geology of evolution, emphasizing short- & long-term mechanisms of organizational transformation, some of which are rooted in natural (e.g., geological sequences) & immemorial times (culture), while others follow the financial, political or daily timesFootnote 23.

In sum, what is the ‘Council on the Future’? Here we emphasize the Potterian and Leopoldian proposal for a new socio-philosophical organization of our ways of thinking, linking Science, Humanities and Communities (Jurić, 2017; Sultonbekovich, 2022)—and distancing them from the reductionist idea of a mere material world unit (e.g., an instituted committee). Although we underline the need for synthesis in Complex Theory (as a conceptualization tool, Wilson, 2014; Stoeklé et al., 2020), our emphasis here is on the constructive, prospective and even normative value of synthesis for building awareness of the context (Boudreau LeBlanc, 2023; Latour, 2007): what we call ‘hybridization’Footnote 24. In practice, this Potterian Council draws its inspiration from the ‘Applied Sciences’, fundamentally translational (theories-practices), which emerged at the time of Leopold. Thus, the perspective calls bioethics to move beyond the hegemonic intellectual culture of Principlism in biomedicine (the sacralised Principle-based approach: Autonomy, Beneficence, Non-maleficence, and Justice)Footnote 25. Our argument recalls Potter’s initial claim for a Bio-Ethics bridge, i.e., to develop principles hybridizing biological fact and ethical value. This implies an even deeper philosophical challenge, because it requires us to move beyond the ‘wicked’ synthesizes in ethics (as Principlism is a hybrid of Utilitarianism and Deontological approaches) to a ‘strong’ knowledge hybrid, as qualified by Manfred Max-Neef (1932–2019, 2005) in his framework on Transdisciplinarity.

Preparing the social and ethical terrain

In Reassembling the Social (2007), Latour revitalizes the meaning of Sociology. According to Latour, ‘socio-logy’ is, all at once, a reasoning, a topic, and a collective: respectively,

  1. 1.

    The rationality of a discipline (-logical),

  2. 2.

    A dimension of existence (social), and

  3. 3.

    The set of actors building and using this knowledge (sociologists).

These distinctions (discipline, dimension, and in-action) are not unique to sociology. They apply to all fields of knowledge: from the classic (e.g., biology and ethics) to interdisciplinary hybrids such as ecology and bioethics. And they help to operationalize this Potterian “Council on the Future”.

John Law (2004), in After Methods: Mess in Social Science Research, applies the (socio-organizational) Latourian perspective to the intellectual (metho-epistemological) environment. Methods in sciences are in a constant process of (re)assembling. We find several examples in the literature on Transdisciplinarity and Sustainability, under the approaches of ‘action-research’ (Piovesan, 2022), and ‘community-based research’ (Jason and Glenwick, 2016), of this need for agility and reflexivity between theory (methodologies) and practice (technics and protocols) when applying it in situ (Emerson and Gerlak, 2014; Kemp and Loorbach, 2006; Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2022b). While sometimes quantitative, qualitative, or even mixed approaches are the best suited methodological design, other times a pure objective-natural science (Holling, 1973), a comprehensive ethnocultural graph (Driessen, 2012), or an encompassing rational-empirical synthesis hybridizing both is the best fitting (Ives, 2014). For far too long, we have over-emphasized laboratory experiments (medical and engineering) and promoted models outside the world. Ecology—and recently the COVID pandemics—raises awareness of the fact that we cannot understand the world (e.g., the ecosystem) exclusively from the perspective of a test tube (the in vitro experiment); we need to walk the terrain and accept compromises, i.e., we need a strong awareness of our research objective, the resources at our disposal and previous studies by our peers (including by the community). As Potter noted (1988), this Philosophy of Science’s ecological understanding justifies exploring the operational path of constructivism in and about sciences, i.e., ‘deconstructing’ methods in (rational) ethics to ‘reconstruct’ them with (empirical) in situ one in light of Leopold and Potter’s view of environmental managementFootnote 26.

First, ethics is a discipline. The ‘object’ of study is value, i.e., the objective of empirical ethics research is generally to describe, understand or prioritize a set of values characterizing a case. However, field ethicists go beyond this value-based appreciative advice. After the study of the emerging system of (local) values, they highlight the underlying (social) qualities that give the axis to decision-making (i.e., its meaning, orientations, directions, etc.)Footnote 27. In philosophy, rational studies in ethics focus on theorizing the meta-reasoning behind a value system (the ‘Why’) that explains the – let’s say – good sense to human actions. Second, ethics is a dimension. This ‘axiological’ dimension generates a psycho-intellectual environment per se from which emerges critical thinking and standpointsFootnote 28. These standpoints vary according to several rational factors driven by the person’s reflexivity, cultural identity, and intellectual curriculum. Third, ethics is in-action. This third facet is the key to address one of the arising practical challenges. Ethics must scale up from a cognitive to a collective attribute. Beyond virtuous good willing people, we need good valuable policies. This means scaling up critical thinking from the individual ‘I’ to the collective ‘we’, as the intellectual functioning enters the social-organizational level. Interpersonal dialogues remain the primary unit to foster critical thinking and empower organizations (Widdershoven et al., 2009; Groot and Abma, 2022). The process leading to constructive criticism needs methods to scale dialogues to interinstitutional mediation and translation systems. Appendix 2 gives the framework designed in three iterative analytical phases to assemble methods for conducting a 5-year PhD project in experimental bioethics on antimicrobial governance and data ethics.

Learning from the organization sociology field and a 5-year experience in global bioethics, preparing the terrain for more resilience is crucial. The ‘terrain’ means guiding ecologically, socially and ethically scientific projects with the potential to influence policymaking and societal programs. And the pooling of all the knowledge on how to prepare and reassemble the terrain (Latour, 2007) should become our Council on the Future highlighted by Potter as a ‘Science for Survival’ (1971). ‘Preparing’ requires:

  1. 1.

    A theoretical approach & models to deepen critical reasoning to manage ethical dilemmas.

  2. 2.

    A large-scale method to guide authorities in building transparent policies & critical evaluations to advance governance in adopting a responsible management process.

  3. 3.

    A practice enacted by / within the community focusing on both A- the hazards and B- the impacts of decisions & the managing process.

Operationalizing Global Bioethics appears as a Council or even a toolbox for trained (bio)ethicists valuable to assist governance bodies and communitiesFootnote 29. However, bioethics and bioethicists do not have the capacity or responsibility to identify or solve all ethical issues globally. Fields of natural, social, and human sciences contribute to ethics by improving knowledge of human beings, behaviors, and actions, and the surrounding factors influencing power and will, even human survival, as outlined by Potter. Bioethicists need to learn from methods in global, multisite, and network ethnography (Jarzabkowski et al., 2015; Berthod et al., 2017; Gille and Riain, 2002), and to acknowledge more cleverly critical thinking in systems from individuals (Abma et al., 2010) to the organizational scale (Samuel et al., 2019) with a focus on concerns (Driessen, 2012), tensions (Frauenberger et al., 2017) and integrations (Wilson, 2014; Ives, 2014). However, empirical bioethics is not just about data and quantification but also about critical reflexivity (Ives, 2014; Earp et al., 2020; Zeiler and De Boer, 2020). In short, we should integrate local thinking and experimentalism into global bioethics:

  1. 1.

    Thought experiment aiming to give sense to human action,

  2. 2.

    Consensus-building deliberation to shape value systems for societal transformation.

In practice, this turn starts by having global bioethicists in the field working with sociologists (as called by Latour 2007), other experts, and communities on building—public, civic, corporate, and academic—eco-social responsibility toward the future (see the call from Sustainability studies led by management sciences, Jacob Dahl, 2019). However, this movement driven by the practices milieu in Society must also come from the theoretical spheres in academia reorganizing the structure of disciplines (see the call for a One Heath convergence, Beever and Morar, 2019; Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2022a; Frauenberger et al., 2017; Earp et al., 2020). However, to accomplish this task, the bioethicist should have a toolbox.

The Toolbox of Global Bioethics

Using a common language is the cornerstone for experts and non-experts bounding. It can unwind complex human situations when built on the target audience’s terminological and ontological jargon. For instance, the ‘What’s In It For Me’ (WIIFM), a leading marketing tactic in corporate communications, can help illustrate this idea. The me must become us to allow for synergies and ‘win-win strategies’, another business tactic. Callon provides a deeper understanding of WIIFM (1986). Accordingly, the me is unbreakable of the us (Bilodeau and Potvin, 2018; Fox, 2000; Bou Saba, 2011; Esmonde, 2018). All me.s are networked in the social area, generating controversies while discourses are shocked. More subtly, the me can be a whole institution (Boudreau LeBlanc and Williams-Jones, 2022), as a public, academic, and private moral person carrying a (justificatory) position—e.g., role, interest, and mission—characterizing the Government, University or Business actors (Boudreau LeBlanc and Williams-Jones, 2022).

Depending on the positioning of each actor (Boudreau LeBlanc and Williams-Jones, 2022) and the problematization coined by their collective, specific alliances arise, and the interessement process beginsFootnote 30 (Callon, 1986). Problematization is about common resources, such as the management of the St-Brieuc Bay Scallops (Callon, 1986), or new databases, such as PULSAR (Santé Durable [Sustainable Health] Université Laval) and GloBI (Global Biotic Interactions). And one problematization can lead to another, such as building public-private-academic collaborative partnerships and sustaining trust or conducting responsible research and innovation. These needs pulse the movement, engagement, and commitment, thus an enrolment phase. Callon acknowledges enrolment as “a set of strategies in which the researchers [or the entity in charge of stabilizing the initiative] sought to define and interrelate the various roles they had allocated to others” (1986, p.1). However, these self-interested alliances do not happen by themselves. Building on Callon’s theory, the paper emphasizes the need for translation tools in ethics and for collaborative governance to provide a common “roof” to co-operate, which might appear as an agreement of governance, evaluation, and research principles.

The path towards translation is framed by “Obligatory Points of Passage” (OPP). OPP benefits from the presence of researchers, as they “determined a set of actors and defined their identities in such a way as to establish themselves in the network of relationships they were building” (Callon, 1986, p.6). We argue for having OPP in a strategic milieu, as data arbitration centers, to open debate on resolving controversies by sharing information between expert and non-expert perspectives (Boudreau LeBlanc, 2022). Dialogue on data governance advances the idea of ‘hybrid forums’ and ‘hybrid communities’ by sophisticating the negotiation process (see Appendix 1), for instance, by mutualizing health and environment surveillance data to negotiate an ever-more sustainable path to manage the issue. When set before a crisis, hybrid forums engage and deepen the discourses of a controversy. Those places could highlight the underlying ethical values and application paths (Boudreau LeBlanc and Williams-Jones, 2022). Introducing bioethics to Latourian thinking could favor mobilization (Petersen, 2013; Williams-Jones and Graham, 2003). According to Callon, mobilization is the assemblage of “a set of methods used by the researchers to ensure that supposed spokesmen for various relevant collectivities were properly able to represent those collectivities and not betrayed by the latter” (1986, p.1). In short, Callon et al., 2001 propose a reflexive translational path to transform intangible social processes into tangible political-methodological strategies to act collectively.

Having in dialogue the Me(s) should not offload responsibility onto one another. The goal is to sketch pathways through a deliberation process with two (social) parties involved: the experts and ‘spokespersons’ of the community. Instead of a hybrid forum, let’s propose the synthetic idea of WIIFU-M: ‘What’s In It For Us-Me’? The Us-Me is a nod to the Latourian social theory developed between 1980 and 2000 – the Actor-Network Theory. The WIIFU-M allows for a shift from an individual ethics to a collective one (Bilodeau and Potvin, 2018; Piovesan, 2022; Jacob Dahl, 2019). Moreover, it lays the foundation for a frame of reference to assist managers in sharing responsibilities. Ultimately, the “including me” can result in one party taking responsibility for another (e.g., vulnerable, invisible, or non-human communities).

One of the challenges of complexity is to manage knowledge, as West Churchman (1913–2004, 1967) introduced with the concept of the ‘Wicked problem’. Wicked problems are like a puzzle where a piece is always missing, notably because the boundaries constantly change. The logic of solving a wicked problem is: “[…] to shift the goal of action on significant problems from ‘solution’ to ‘intervention’. Instead of seeking the answer that totally eliminates a problem, one should recognize that actions occur in a process, and further actions will always be needed.” (Knapp, 2008) These problems lead to some challenges, notably the bridging of Science and Policy, because they:

[…] are not only difficult to define, there exist no right or wrong solutions for them, only better or worse solutions because they involve competing goals, divergent values, little scientific agreement on cause-effect relationships, imperfect information, and inequitable distribution of political power in implementing and influencing planning (Hull, 2009).

Accordingly, one key Philosophy or Science advanced is the logic of adaptive and learning cycles. Adaptability traits should be archived in a translational unit to enable ‘learning’. Susan Star (1954–2010; 2010) Star and Greisemer, 1989) coins the concept of ‘boundary-object’ (BO, see also Loorbach et al.’s perspective on transition, 2016), introducing a vehicle for knowledge transfers and social dialogues. Figure 2 applies BO to Max-Neef (2005)’s theoretical framework of transdisciplinarity. Transdisciplinarity unpacks the organization of translation (Chursinova et al., 2022; Beever and Whitehouse, 2017). At the same time, the BO helps conceive the vehicle bridging Sciences, Humanities and Society, which is outlined by Potter as a “Bridge to the Future” (1971) and the ‘wisdom’ of a ‘Future-Oriented Human Council’ (ten Have, 2012; Langlois, 2013).

Fig. 2: The Future-Oriented Human Council.
figure 2

Using boundary-objects to develop a system of knowledge that is bridging the Facts/Values complex unit and the theories’ translation/practices’ experimentalism could help imaging the Potterian Future-Oriented Human Council. However, we need to reorganise our ways of thinking, in particular by proposing OBs for recruiting allies (the bottom up, close to practices, the ‘micro'), others for advancing controversies between applied sciences (the midway translation, close to institutional missions, the ‘meso') and the last for developing the reasoning of fundamental sciences in response to the living experience of the world (the top down, positing the philosophy of science in dialogue with the common, the traditional and the culture, the ‘macro/meta').

Translation paths must interconnect abductively theory and practices, as Charles Peirce (1839–1914), Karl Popper (1922–1996), Kuhn and several others explain. However, those paths must seek to bridge applied disciplines under the same rooftop (a hybrid of facts and values). On the one hand, technics and practices improve individual, populational, and community operations, while values give it sense, e.g., Care & Biodiversity. Thus, Potter calls for a new object of study that unpacks this classical boundary between Science and Ethics disciplines (‘boundary-objects’, BO). As Callon sketches, these BO generates a system (BOs) whose organization of knowledge is the very object of the Sociology of translation. When researchers enter the field, the BOs materialize itself as a habitat of knowledge (ecoBOs). However, concerned citizens should be empowered and capable of managing the use of the ecoBOs. We argue the need for bioethics and bioethicist to remain alert of the risk of radical knowledge shift, as introduced by Daniel Callahan (1930–2019) when facts are used without their corresponding sense (Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2021a; Callahan, 1973).

BO are not absolute (ontological) knowledge. If the frame stays the same, the BO content varies with time depending on environmental, technological, anthropological, sociological, and intellectual changes. For instance, the BO of ‘social and ecosystem services’ frames anthropology and ecology in the jargon of economy (Peçanha Enqvist et al., 2018; Brand and Jax, 2007; Abson et al., 2014). A BO provides a working theories, which is setting a frame-to-work (a framework) from one discipline to another (Morar, 2019; Osorio, 2017; Mertz and Schildmann, 2018). For instance, organizational ‘resilience’ has bridged Baltimore, Chicago, and Mining Schools, and advanced urban ecology, planning and care under the ecological and ecosystem metaphor (the ‘ecosystemic’). However, to build intellectual bridges in practice, we need well-done working theories to prepare the terrain.

Conclusion

The ecosystemic approach could bridge medical & environmental fields and practices in managing Care, Production & Biodiversity. However, some epistemological challenge remains. We argue that reviewing the Potterian and Leopoldian views of Biology and Ethics may help. Both authors valued codes of conduct (The Land Ethic and A Bioethical Creed). Still, this normative knowledge should not be used dogmatically, as a legal unit or a static theory pulsing top-down power dynamics. The Potterian Creed is built on experience, supported by communication and served societal projects envisioning a better future. In these times of crisis, global bioethics scholars should open a large-scale thinking program on the place and application of the Leopoldian adaptive ecosystem co-management technics and philosophy in medical & environmental fields and practices. Accordingly, the author has studied this perspective since 2018 at the level of information and communication technology systems by improving the operation of policies regarding the adoption and management of digital environments, data networks, and artificial intelligence (Boudreau LeBlanc, 2022; Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2021b; Bérubé et al., 2022). The work of bioethics critically examines the value of working theories as they are operated and constructed as boundary objects (Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2021a; Boudreau LeBlanc, 2022). The role of fieldwork bioethicists is to develop tools and their justificatory reasoning (Boudreau LeBlanc et al., 2022c) to help concerned researchers, leaders, and citizens to own the wheel of change.