This page has been archived and is no longer updated

 

Valuing Ecosystems

By: Bryan G. Norton (Ph.D. in Philosophy; Distinguished Professor of Public Policy, Georgia Institute of Technology) © 2012 Nature Education 
Citation: Norton, B. G. (2012) Valuing Ecosystems. Nature Education Knowledge 3(10):2
Email
Humans value natural systems in many ways. Should all of these values be expressed in economic terms? Or, do ecosystems have value independent of humans?
Aa Aa Aa

 

Norton banner.

What is the value of an intact, healthy ecosystem? This question may seem odd: on the one hand, humans are animals and we depend upon our physical and living systems — our habitat — for our very existence, so one might say the value of ecosystems is virtually infinite — there should be no limit to the value humans place on their life-support system. On the other hand, unless this question is explicitly posed, most humans hardly think about the many contributions ecosystems make to everyday lives because they are so pervasive as to be unnoticed, and because we encounter many of those contributions in forms obscured by human transformations — toilet tissue is transformed trees! Nevertheless, charting a rational policy toward protecting and sustaining the human environment requires that we recognize the huge contribution of ecological systems to human well-being, and that we consider not only the marketable products derived from those systems, but also the more intangible values, such as spiritual and noninstrumental values.

To choose appropriate protectionist policies, we must know how to evaluate changes in the state of ecosystems that result from actual and proposed actions and policies. The most common approaches to such evaluation are aggregative; they begin by identifying and estimating the value of elements or aspects of a natural system and attributing value to its parts. On these approaches, the value of larger systems, is estimated by aggregating the value of parts: the value of whole systems is the sum of the values of their parts.

Part 1: Aggregating Elements of Value

Despite the dominance of aggregative approaches, no unified approach to valuing ecosystems has emerged. There is a split in the discourse about environmental value; practitioners of different disciplines aggregate very different units of value; for example, economists evaluate actual and possible consumable units, while environmental ethicists value habitats and ecosystems as important units. Mainstream environmental economics and the dominant, nonanthropocentric school of environmental ethics, the two academic disciplines most likely to provide insights regarding natural value, despite sharing an aggregative approach, are at odds regarding the nature of environmental value. Consequently there has emerged no common method for evaluating environmental change. This disagreement has so far blocked the emergence of a unified discourse, or a unified method, for evaluating environmental change. In the remainder of this Section, these two aggregative approaches will be discussed and compared.

1.1 Environmental Economics

Environmental economists measure environmental value by identifying "commodities" — units of goods and services derived from nature that can be purchased in markets. Economists measure preferences of individuals as behaviorally measurable "willingness-to-pay" ("wtp") and then use these prices as a guide to the welfare individual consumers seek. In the standard case, consumers signal their preference for a commodity and the individual welfare associated with it by purchasing units of that commodity, while balancing the unit price against all of the other preferences they have. These preferences are revealed in the purchase of commodities

While economists are most comfortable when their estimates of price values are revealed in actual behaviors, either direct or indirect, they also recognize that there are many things of value — especially natural systems and their parts — that are seldom traded in markets. Economists have therefore extended their effort to evaluate aspects of nature that have "non-market" value by supplementing revealed preferences with stated preference methods (Krutilla, 1967). Stated preference methods, spoken of generally as "contingent valuation studies," are designed to elicit estimates of individuals' wtp for a commodity if it were available in markets (Mitchell and Carson, 1993; Freeman, 2003). Techniques can involve bidding games, interviews, questionnaires, etc., and their purpose is to represent the wtp value of commodities, such as improved views in a national park or the knowledge that polar bears can continue to exist in the Arctic, even though the valuer never expects to visit the Arctic. Economists have thus greatly expanded the range of goods and services that can be considered to be "environmental values."

This approach, anchored in the traditional concept of market prices as behavioral indicators of individual value, and supplemented by contingent valuations of nonmarket goods, has encouraged some to evaluate environmental change as increments or decrements in the aggregated wtp's of all relevant consumers. On this approach, the value of ecosystems can be represented as an aggregation of the commodity-values that all consumers can derive, directly or indirectly, from those systems. To evaluate a proposed or actual change in an ecosystem, one would simply aggregate and compare the total commodity-values available to humans before and after the change.

Thinking of the problem of ecosystem valuation in this way may encourage basing evaluations of actions using a "Cost-Benefit Analysis" (CBA). In the extreme case, some advocates of this approach claim or imply that it should be possible in principle to list all the costs and benefits of a given policy or action, and thus to make decisions based strictly on a monetary criterion whereby the best policy is the one that exhibits the largest ratio of benefits to costs. Such optimism, however, is belied by the daunting task of identifying all the possible commodities that would have to be listed and estimated, and by the apparent inability of measures of economic preference to express many of our values, including values felt for loved ones or deeply spiritual commitments to natural places. In fact, no practitioners have claimed to have completed this daunting task in even one case, and most advocates of economic aggregation in the valuing of ecosystems suggest a CBA as only a starting point, a partial accounting that helps to call attention to valued items and to possible risks of loss (Freeman, 2003). Thus the bold promise of providing an accounting of ecosystem values in a single, aggregative measure recedes. What is left is recognition that economic values are of course relevant and important in evaluating changes in ecosystems, but an accompanying sense that these methods must be supplemented with a great deal of either hand-waving over gaps, or a commitment to temper any economic indicators with a great deal of judgment and good sense.

1.2 Ecological Economics and Ecosystem Services

By the middle of the 1980s, a number of economists and ecologists, expressing doubts about the ability of standard economic analyses (in terms of wtp) to capture the whole range of values humans derive from ecosystems, created a transdisciplinary field of "ecological economics" (Gomez-Baggethun et al., 2010) At first, ecological economists criticized mainstream economists for ignoring ecological principles and the importance of the scale of impacts on ecosystems, but ecological economists did not go beyond the standard economic methods of measuring market and nonmarket values. Then, frustrated by the lack of awareness of how ecological systems and processes support human well-being and the failure of economists to take into account the regulative functions that stabilize systems and allow human adaptation to them, it was suggested that ecologists could identify processes that provide "services" to human beings (Daily, 1997; World Health Organization, 2005). The idea of "ecosystem services" has rapidly gained in popularity and it is now a widely used concept in the evaluation of ecosystems.

This concept is clearly important in raising awareness of human dependencies on nature as it includes three major areas of services: 1. Provisioning (food and fiber); 2. Regulation (maintenance of energy flows and maintaining resilience of systems): and 3. Cultural ecosystem services (such as the values of place). While cultural ecological services are regularly mentioned, few methods exist for either characterizing or measuring these values.

Efforts have been made to estimate the total value humans derive from ecosystem services (Costanza et al., 1997) and ecological economists have been criticized for introducing monetized measures that are not based on the methodologies of mainstream economics, creating ambiguity in the measures used. These controversies, however, need not obviate the usefulness of ecosystem services as long as one does not aggregate monetized ecosystem service estimates with the wtp values of mainstream environmental economists. Ecosystem service identifications will be seen to be an important aspect of more procedural approaches to evaluation in Section 2, below.

1.3 Environmental Ethics

The approach that aggregates commodity values to indicate the value of nature to humans is strongly criticized by environmental ethicists who insist that all measures of economic value are unacceptably anthropocentric, based on the utilitarian theory that all value can be represented as human welfare. According to environmental ethicists, what morally demands protection in ecosystems is not value instrumental to human well-being, but values intrinsic to nature itself. These ethicists believe that elements of nature have intrinsic values and that these values often trump values instrumental to humans.

Nonanthropocentrists attribute intrinsic value to natural entities: some identify individual organisms, others identify species, and others ecological systems as the loci of such value (Taylor, 1986; Rolston, III, 1988; Callicott, 1989). In whichever case this approach aggregates the value of elements of nature that are taken to have intrinsic value. While there is little agreement about how, exactly, to keep the books with respect to intrinsic value, intrinsic value theorists aggregate toward decisions by maximizing the protection and flourishing of all elements of nature, human and nonhuman, which have intrinsic value.

The confrontation between environmental economists and environmental ethicists has blocked the emergence of a unified approach to evaluating ecological change because each attempts to aggregate and maximize a single value — human welfare and total intrinsic value, respectively — and these values are apparently incommensurable. As a result, discussions of ecosystem values are polarized around two opposing theories about the nature of ecological value. No unified field or discipline for evaluating ecological change has emerged.

Perhaps neither of these aggregative approaches is likely to succeed in unifying the discourse of ecological valuation. Unless this intellectual dilemma is somehow resolved, the future of valuing ecosystems is likely to remain in chaos. Aggregative approaches are monistic: they assume that ecosystematic values can be expressed in a single currency. Since they advocate incommensurable values, however, no final accounting is possible. The poor performance of monists in evaluating change, and the intellectual dilemmas created by the interaction of economists and ethicists have led a number of environmental theorists to explore moral pluralism.

According to moral pluralism, humans value nature in many ways not easily made commensurate, but all of these values are important and the goal should be to find an adequate balance in protecting multiple values rather than trying to maximize a single value. Pluralism does not offer a single best answer, but rather seeks a fair and reasonable balance among competing values. Pluralism, however, is not conducive to aggregation, so commitment to pluralism suggests an alternative to aggregative approaches.

Part 2: Process Approaches: Alternatives to Aggregation

Today, a second approach to evaluating change, a "participative/process" approach, shifts the unit of analysis from particular changes to ecosystem to possible "development paths" or "scenarios." On this approach, no attempt is made to provide a single total value of the system; rather, by associating changes to ecosystems with various policies, evaluation can be carried out as a ranking of possible choices — holistically interpreted as possible development paths — according to expected outcomes affecting an ecosystem. This ranking is addressed by representative members of the affected society who, first, choose evaluative criteria representing values considered important by the participants (which operationalizes pluralism) and, second, rank possible outcomes as preferred or less preferred according to the list of criteria (Norton, 2005).

What is different between the aggregative approach and the process approach — besides the pluralism with respect to values of the latter — is that the process approach depends upon movement toward consensus in action, rather than trying to calculate or compute a correct answer based on aggregation of a single kind of values.

The process approach, sometimes called "adaptive management" or "adaptive collaborative management," thus, directs its attention toward the development of improved processes of deliberation, and considers decisions "rational" as long as they were arrived at by an "appropriate process" (Simon, 1979: O'Neill et al., 2008). This approach, then, seems more appropriate in democratic societies that value nature in diverse ways, and it encourages social learning and public deliberation about what is important enough to monitor and to save.

While it might be thought that one must choose between aggregative and process approaches, it turns out that the techniques and tools developed for aggregating goods can play a role — a somewhat different role — in public deliberative processes. As described above, aggregative analyses seek to provide, on the basis of careful analysis, a best solution to a problem affecting ecosystems; this analysis occurs independently of political and social processes. For them, the external analysis means that public processes should be manipulated to get "the right answer." Those who reject aggregation, on the other hand, do not believe there is one correct solution, so they emphasize developing free and fair processes that allow incremental learning about what is possible and what is valuable. Process-oriented evaluators can thus incorporate economic and environmental considerations into the deliberative discourse, where the test of theory is its usefulness in reaching consensus. Likewise, the concept of ecosystem services becomes important; identification and articulation of human dependencies on nature can be an important aspect of learning in adaptive, collaborative processes. So the concept of ecosystem services, if properly embedded in a social and political process can be an important tool in a process-oriented, incremental learning approach to ecological management.

Conclusion

Nobody questions that ecosystems are valuable; but there is considerable disagreement about how to assess and express these values. This disagreement reflects underlying differences in theories of environmental value. Among those who pursue the aggregative strategy, conflict separates them into disciplinary camps, with economists aggregating only over human values, while environmental ethicists insist that the well-being of some nonhumans should be included in evaluations of ecological systems. Because this debate is so intractable, as opponents try to enforce their monistic theory of value, an alternative approach, which accepts pluralism and pays attention to processes by which communities can balance and trade off among competing values, is gaining in acceptance.

References and Recommended Reading


Callicott, J.B. In Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press (1989).

Costanza, R., d'ARge, R., de Groot, Rudolf, Farber, S., Grasso, M., Hannon, B., Limburg, K., Naeem, S., O'Neill, R.V., Paruelo, H., Raskin, R.G., Sutton, P., and van den Belt, M., The value of the world's ecosystem services and natural capital. Nature 387, 253-260 (1987).

Daily, G.C. Nature's Services: Societal Dependence on Natural Ecosystems. Washington, DC: Island Press (1997).

Gomez-Baggethun, E., de Groot, R., Lomas, P.L., and Montes, C. "The history of ecosystem services in economic theory and practice: From early notions to markets and Payment Schemes. Ecological Economics 69, 1209-1218 (2010).

Freeman, A.M. The Measurement of Environmmental and Resource Values: Theory and Method (2nd Edition) Washington, DC: Resources for the Future (2003).

Krutilla, J.V. Conservation reconsidered. The American Economic Review 57, 777-786 (1967).

World Health Organization Millennium Ecosystem Assessment. Ecosystems and Human Well-Being. Geneva, Switzerland (2005).

Mitchell, R. and Carson, R.T. Using Surveys to Value Public Goods: The Contingent Valuation Method. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future (1993).

Norton, BG. Sustainability: A Philosophy of Adaptive Ecosystem Management Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press (2005).

O'Neill, J., Holland, A., and Light, A. Environmental Values London: Routledge (2008).

Rolston, III, H. Environmental Ethics: Duties to the Natural World. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press 1988).

Simon, H. From substantive to procedural rationality. In Philosophy and Economic Theory Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press (1979).

Taylor, P. Respect for Nature. New York: Oxford University Press (1986).

Email

Flag Inappropriate

This content is currently under construction.

Connect
Connect Send a message


Nature Education Home

Environmental Ethics

Visual Browse

Close