Denial of scientific evidence and rejection of scientific methods are not new phenomena, but represent an increasingly serious problem, especially when driven by politically well-connected and well-funded antagonists seeking to sabotage evidence-based policy for political and/or financial gain. Terms such as ‘science denial’ and ‘science denialism’ are employed as monikers for such anti-scientific enterprises, seeking to discredit, for example, the health impacts of smoking, climate science, the teaching of evolution in schools and vaccination campaigns. There is an emerging body of literature characterizing the nature of these activities, and the personal, organizational and economic interlinkages between them1.

The rise of organized denial of the biodiversity crisis was foreseen by conservation biologists2 and the growing wave of denial finally broke following the release of the Intergovernmental Science-Policy Platform on Biodiversity and Ecosystem Services (IPBES) summary for policymakers which generated substantial media coverage. In its wake, a swathe of opinion pieces criticized the report and attacked both the reputations of the report’s authors and the process of estimating the total number of species threatened with extinction3.

The three categories of denial

These attempts to downplay the biodiversity crisis follow the ‘Scientific Certainty Argumentation Methods’ playbook, which includes all three categories of denial envisioned by Stanley Cohen in a framework first applied to the study of atrocities and other unwelcome truths4. These are: (1) ‘Literal denial’, an assertion that something is untrue, for example the evidence for greatly elevated rates of species threat and extinction; (2) ‘Interpretive denial’, in which raw facts are not disputed but given a different spin, for example using evidence from temperate ecosystems to make claims about reduced impacts in the tropics; (3) ‘Implicatory denial’, in which data are not denied, but implications are, for example arguing that transformative changes to socio–ecological systems are not required to avert species extinctions.

We address each of these in detail, before exploring ways to counter erroneous claims and logical fallacies that we understand to be ‘extinction denialism’ or ‘biodiversity loss denialism’.

Literal denial: ‘Species extinctions were predominantly a historical problem’

Extinction deniers often downplay the extinction crisis by framing it as a historical problem and a trivial contemporary challenge (Supplementary Table 1). By focusing attention on the loss of megafauna in prehistory owing to overhunting and rapid loss of island biodiversity in historic times, it is suggested we have passed through these extinction filters and reached the ‘other side’ of the crisis. This ‘literal denial’ line of argument misses several key facets of the extinction crisis, notably that species, including island endemics, are still being lost5 and that the catastrophic loss, degradation and fragmentation of whole ecosystems, combined with climate change, is triggering a new episode of continental extinctions6. This is particularly acute in the highly biodiverse tropics and where extinctions are just the endpoint of a long process of extirpation and defaunation7 (Box 1, Supplementary Table 2). Moreover, biologists are typically conservative in declaring possible extinctions, and across the world there are 143 amphibians, 41 reptiles, 29 mammals and 22 bird species classed by the International Union for Conservation of Nature (IUCN) Red List of Threatened Species (https://www.iucnredlist.org) as ‘Critically Endangered (Possibly Extinct)’. Many of these species are likely already gone, while many more, including the 75 species listed as ‘Extinct in the Wild’, are only hanging on due to expensive, last resort, conservation interventions8.

Interpretive denial: ‘Economic growth alone will fix the extinction crisis’

Extinction denialists often invoke an Environmental Kuznets Curve (EKC)9 response of biodiversity to development (Supplementary Table 1), arguing that pressures on the environment eventually decrease with rising income levels. Yet the EKC hypothesis is misleading in this context. First, empirical evidence of the relationship between economic development and forest cover only supports the loss part of the curve10. Second, the EKC is typically a local rather than a global phenomenon, and global environmental indicators of indirect impacts such as CO2 emissions, waste production and energy consumption are still increasing monotonically. Country-specific assessments of EKC often ignore the outsourcing of environmental degradation to poorer countries. Denialists also highlight the resurgence of certain large charismatic species such as wolves and bears in Europe and North America as evidence that we are through the worst of the extinction crisis. However, this is only a partial success story (Box 1). Similar successes in the tropics are highly unlikely: species richness, species packing and habitat and niche specialization are all far higher at tropical latitudes, while geographic range sizes are much smaller. These factors mean that tropical biodiversity is far more extinction-prone then temperate biodiversity11. The unfortunate truth is that there are many imminent or actual extinctions in highly deforested tropical regions (Supplementary Table 2). Finally, the so-called ‘Forest Transition’ model9, which envisages an EKC-style relationship between forest cover and development, fails to differentiate between native forests and monoculture plantations of oil palm, conifers and eucalyptus, despite the expansion of plantations being an important cause of biodiversity loss. Many global forest models are not sensitive to the difference12 and conflating plantations with natural forests has long been a key feature of the denialist playbook.

Implicatory denial: ‘Technological fixes and targeted conservation interventions will overcome extinction’

Extinction denialists are often selective, choosing to highlight only a subset of factors causing contemporary extinctions, such as overharvesting and predation by non-native species, while choosing not to mention habitat loss that affects the majority of species on the Red List. They then suggest that solutions are simple, requiring no change or business-as-usual actions, even though it is increasing resource demands and current socio–ecological and economic modes of organization that imperil biodiversity globally7. Invasive species, overharvesting and pathogens are undoubtedly major conservation issues responsible for global extinctions of many — particularly insular — species, and technological fixes form part of the portfolio of conservation interventions. However, these threats are often exacerbated by habitat loss and climate change, and all must be addressed together. A disproportionate focus on a subset of drivers is a form of implicatory denial that is contrary to scientific consensus: recognizing the importance of one set of threats does not obviate the need to address others8. Another form of implicatory denial involves the misrepresentation of the land sharing/sparing concept (Box 1).

Countering denial

There are multiple ways in which conservation scientists can be proactive in countering denial (Table 1). The first is to conduct rigorous science to refine understanding of the scale, scope and causes of the extinction crisis. However, it is not enough just to get the science right, but also to communicate it to a wide audience, working with journalists, artists and other communicators to disseminate the evidence before denialists are able to contrive a consensus gap13. In combating the pseudoscience peddled by denialists it has been argued that the scientific consensus on climate change has been impacted by ‘seepage’, whereby scientists respond to critics by overemphasizing uncertainty, allowing denialist claims to impact how they portray their own research. Where modelled predictions of loss are questioned, it is useful to highlight that empirical observations of extinction risk often outpace predictions14. Confronting polemicists and rhetoricians well-versed in arguing positions rather than establishing truth can be a major challenge. Whilst retaining a cordial dialogue, there is little point in being respectful of insincere arguments, which should be called out for what they are and dismantled and rebutted systematically with evidence3.

Table 1 Communicating biodiversity loss with the public in the context of Fischhoff’s Stages of Risk Communication16

It is important not only to communicate the science of extinction, but also to communicate the implications of biodiversity loss (Table 1). This can be most effective when conservation scientists find ways to demonstrate connections that resonate with a target audience. Examples could include making connections between deforestation, wild animal trade and zoonoses; or between foods people consume daily and their connection to conservation problems and solutions. Care needs to be taken not to exaggerate the importance of minor threats while overlooking major ones. For example, implicatory denial often involves faux-concern about wind farms as a cause of biodiversity loss, despite the evidence that wind energy — while not without negative impacts — is a relatively minor threat compared to habitat loss and climate change, or even the impact of other forms of energy production, such as extraction of shale gas or coal. Here, conservation scientists need to recognize the underlying anti-renewable energy agenda and can respond by putting threats in context. Scientists can provide context on the impacts of wind farms by comparing impacts per unit of electricity produced in different ways. They also have the knowledge to explain and advise on how to further minimize those impacts by proper siting and management.

To generate support for solutions, conservation scientists need to show that similar challenges have been overcome in the past, that the risks are acceptable and that the benefits exceed the costs. It is also necessary to engage people’s emotions, using examples from civil rights to the ozone hole to acid rain to smoking bans. These clearly show that dramatic change is not only possible, but desirable. Denialists find fault with conservationists for failing to report positive news. However, this is a talking point that originates within the conservation community itself, and as a criticism it is now somewhat redundant. Conservationists have called on each other to not only report bad news accurately but also flag up good news stories as best we can15, for example, via https://conservationoptimism.com, but without sugar-coating the broader truth.

Debate is vital as we search for solutions to the biodiversity crisis, but these debates are only useful where there is good will on all sides. For conservation to succeed, it will need to be inclusive, and conservation scientists need to be better at identifying useful discussions and avoiding unnecessary internal conflicts. But in cases when constructive arguments turn into dismissiveness or denial, and when vested interests are prioritized over the search for truth, good will cannot be assumed (Table 1). Unless denialists have a large platform, the best response may be to ignore them to avoid amplifying their efforts at misinformation. For this reason, we have deliberately avoided referencing the names and publications of prominent deniers here in the main text. Where responses are necessary, conservation scientists need to avoid getting dragged down into ugly arguments or personal attacks, be measured and respectful in their responses, and reinforce their role as trusted experts by countering flawed arguments with evidence. By adopting these approaches, and learning some of the lessons of climate denial, conservation scientists can reclaim the narrative.