COMMENT

Don’t deploy negative emissions technologies without ethical analysis

Climate policy advice is being undermined by value-laden choices over risky mitigation strategies, warn Dominic Lenzi and colleagues.
Dominic Lenzi is a researcher at the Mercator Research Institute on Global Commons and Climate Change, Berlin, Germany.
Contact

Search for this author in:

William F. Lamb is a researcher at the Mercator Research Institute on Global Commons and Climate Change, Berlin, Germany.

Search for this author in:

Jérôme Hilaire is a researcher at the Mercator Research Institute on Global Commons and Climate Change, Berlin, Germany, and is at the Potsdam Institute for Climate Impact Research, Germany.

Search for this author in:

Martin Kowarsch is head of scientific assessments, ethics and public policy at the Mercator Research Institute on Global Commons and Climate Change, Berlin, Germany.

Search for this author in:

Jan C. Minx is head of applied sustainability science at the Mercator Research Institute on Global Commons and Climate Change, Berlin, Germany, and is at the School of Earth and Environment, University of Leeds, UK.

Search for this author in:

Carbon capture project at a power plant

A pilot project in Spremberg, Germany, aims to capture carbon dioxide released from power stations. Credit: Action Press/REX/Shutterstock

In October, the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) will release a special report on keeping global temperature rise within 1.5 °C of pre-industrial levels. Governments requested the report at the 2015 Paris climate conference. Policymakers want to know what further steps would be needed to stay well within the 2 °C threshold, above which the risks of climate change become more dangerous.

The IPCC report will confirm an open secret: in the light of growing emissions, targets for mitigating climate change increasingly depend on ‘negative emissions technologies’ that suck carbon dioxide out of the atmosphere. Staying within 2 °C could mean extracting billions of tonnes of CO2 this century.

Atmospheric carbon — captured after burning biofuels, for instance — could be locked in the ground or sea for thousands of years. Forests and soils could be managed to store more carbon. Or more-speculative means that are still in the realm of basic research could be used1. Examples include fertilizing the oceans with iron to enhance phytoplankton growth, increasing the weathering of minerals or developing devices that remove CO2 directly from the air.

“It really throws into question the idea that we’re doing clear-sighted policymaking”

The vast scale at which such technologies would need to be implemented raises ethical concerns. For example, growing more biomass to burn as fuel would take land away from food production and use water for irrigation2. Famines, civil unrest and damage to biodiversity could follow3. Seeding the oceans with iron could undermine marine ecosystems. Covering an area twice the size of the United States with crushed silicate stones to enhance weathering would affect communities, agriculture and ecosystems.

Yet there has been no systematic evaluation of the ethics of carbon removal methods by the climate assessment community or professional philosophers. The IPCC’s latest review (its fifth assessment report) included a chapter on ethics4, setting out concepts of responsibility, justice and welfare. But it did not dwell much on negative emissions technologies, nor did other chapters consider ethics. Carbon removal methods must be ethically evaluated in the context of climate policy pathways.

The key question is, which pathways are most compatible with human rights, sustainable development and environmental protection? The stakes are high. Negative emissions technologies could be a valuable way to avoid dangerous climate change. But they might become an unjust gamble that uses future generations as collateral5.

Missing ethics

Why has this aspect of negative emissions been overlooked? Ethicists neglect the science; modellers neglect the ethics. Geoengineering debates have been dominated by solar-radiation management — altering the reflectivity of the whole atmosphere seems more dystopian than growing forests or storing carbon. Early studies suggested that negative emissions technologies were largely benign6. Growing dependence on negative emissions increases the risks, but most ethicists have not noted this shift.

Aerial view of a palm oil plantation in the Democratic Republic of the Congo

A palm-oil plantation in the Democratic Republic of the Congo encroaches on nearby rainforest areas.Credit: Daniel Beltrá/Greenpeace

Philosophical discussions of climate change revolve around abstract principles: the ‘common but differentiated responsibilities of states’ to fund mitigation and adaptation, whether the polluter pays and who has the ability to pay. The debates do not consider particular policy pathways, telling us little about what a just future would look like or how to achieve it. Without interrogating mitigation pathways, ethics will be of little use for policy assessment.  

Ethicists need a better understanding of climate-mitigation research. The vast scales over which negative emissions technologies would be unleashed are difficult to grasp. Even the climate stabilization target isn’t settled. It seems obvious that lower temperatures are ethically preferable. But getting negative emissions wrong also raises risks. Keeping within 1.5 °C of warming could cause side effects that are as bad as those in a world that is 2 °C warmer — such as through environmental damage caused by ramping up mineral mining, or cutting down the rest of the Amazon rainforest for biofuels.

Values in disguise

Meanwhile, modellers inevitably make value-laden assumptions in charting different policy pathways, including the range of options being considered, such as rapid technological development or nuclear energy. Assumptions also include the political, economic and demographic stories behind them, such as steady population growth or declining international cooperation. For example, the IPCC included negative emissions technologies in its ‘default’ technology mix, even though some of these solutions might never be viably scaled up7.

A lack of transparency and ethical discussion has three consequences. First, policymakers have false expectations. This is the ‘moral hazard’ worry: if politicians and advisers think it is acceptable to emit carbon now and claw it back later, they might take more risks and obstruct mitigation in the real world8. For example, in IPCC scenarios with CO2 retrieval, emissions from fossil fuels and industry can remain as high as 32 gigatonnes of CO2 in 2030 (see ‘Three-fold folly’, top panel). Without CO2 removal, emissions would have to be reduced to 23 gigatonnes of CO2 by 2030 — a difference almost equivalent to China’s emissions each year since 2008.

Sources: Top panel: K. Riahi et al. Technol. Forecast. Soc. Change 90 (A), 8–23 (2015); Bottom panel: C. Le Quere et al. Earth Syst. Sci. Data 10, 405–448 (2018).

Second, designing climate policy around technologies that might never scale up is risky7. A typical 2 °C climate scenario requires the funding, construction and operation of as many as 16,000 plants that combine biomass burning with carbon capture and storage by 2050. Today there are three demonstration projects (see ‘Three-fold folly’, middle panel). If the bet fails, future generations will face a carbon overdraft and warming that is greater than 2 °C3.

Third, implementing negative emissions at the scales envisaged is ambitious, to say the least5. According to many models, this would mean managing an artificial carbon sink that is larger than the entire land sink today (see ‘Three-fold folly’, bottom panel). Assessments also must not ignore a host of potential feedback mechanisms and tipping points that are poorly understood, such as whether temperature overshoot might trigger permafrost melting9.  

Draw on diverse views

A cultural change is required across the climate-change community. As for human-participants research in bioscience, ethicists need to be involved from the outset in developing, modelling and evaluating scenarios for reducing emissions. The IPCC should integrate the perspectives of these experts across all chapters of its reports. There are no plans to do this within the sixth IPCC review currently in preparation.

To broaden the range of considerations included, we would like to see ethicists, modellers and social scientists, governments and civil-society groups collaborate on climate-mitigation assessments. Drawing on divergent viewpoints and criteria, they should map the various implications of alternative policy pathways10. Organizations such as the Integrated Assessment Modeling Consortium should openly discuss ethical assumptions built into models. This might help to avoid misleading or opaque choices being made at the design stage. For example, lifestyle changes such as meat-free diets or avoidance of aeroplane travel have been absent until recently from scenarios, leading to an imbalanced representation of options11.

Jointly assessing the desirability of alternative futures against ethical principles and the policy goals underlying sustainable development would facilitate critical reflection on negative emissions. Funding bodies such as the European Commission, Future Earth, the US National Science Foundation and other supporters of interdisciplinary research must integrate ethical and social analyses with climate scenario modelling and policy evaluation.

How else can we debate the sort of future we want?

Nature 561, 303-305 (2018)

doi: 10.1038/d41586-018-06695-5
Nature Briefing

Sign up for the daily Nature Briefing email newsletter

Stay up to date with what matters in science and why, handpicked from Nature and other publications worldwide.

Sign Up

References

  1. 1.

    Nemet, G. F. et al. Environ. Res. Lett. 13, 063003 (2018).

  2. 2.

    Creutzig, F. et al. Glob. Change Biol. Bioenergy 7, 916–944 (2015).

  3. 3.

    Shue, H. J. Hum. Rights Environ. 8, 203–216 (2017).

  4. 4.

    Kolstad, C. et al. in Climate Change 2014: Mitigation of Climate Change. Contribution of Working Group III to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (eds Edenhofer, O. et al.) Ch. 3, 207–282 (Cambridge Univ. Press, 2014).

  5. 5.

    Lenzi, D. Glob. Sustain. 1, e7 (2018)

  6. 6.

    Shepherd, J. et al. Geoengineering the Climate: Science, Governance and Uncertainty (Royal Soc., 2009).

  7. 7.

    Fuss, S. et al. Nature Clim. Change 4, 850–853 (2014)

  8. 8.

    Minx, J. C. et al. Environ. Res. Lett. 13, 063001 (2018).

  9. 9.

    Fuss, S. et al. Environ. Res. Lett. 13, 063002 (2018).

  10. 10.

    Kowarsch, M. et al. Nature Clim. Change 7, 379–382 (2017).

  11. 11.

    Creutzig, F. et al. Nature Clim. Change 8, 260–263 (2018).

Download references