Abstract
A large literature suggests that people are intuitive Dualists—they tend to perceive the mind as ethereal, distinct from the body. Here, we ask whether Dualism emanates from within the human psyche, guided, in part, by theory of mind (ToM). Past research has shown that males are poorer mind-readers than females. If ToM begets Dualism, then males should exhibit weaker Dualism, and instead, lean towards Physicalism (i.e., they should view bodies and minds alike). Experiments 1–2 show that males indeed perceive the psyche as more embodied—as more likely to emerge in a replica of one’s body, and less likely to persist in its absence (after life). Experiment 3 further shows that males are less inclined towards Empiricism—a putative byproduct of Dualism. A final analysis confirms that males’ ToM scores are lower, and ToM scores further correlate with embodiment intuitions (in Experiments 1–2). These observations (from Western participants) cannot establish universality, but the association of Dualism with ToM suggests its roots are psychological. Thus, the illusory mind–body divide may arise from the very workings of the human mind.
Similar content being viewed by others
Introduction
A large literature suggests that people are intuitive Dualists—they tend to consider the mind as ethereal, distinct from the body1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16,17. For example, people believe that one’s psychological traits (e.g., thinking about one’s wife) can persist in the afterlife, without one’s body18,19. Conversely, if one’s body were to be duplicated, the replica, people state, would preserve one’s physical characteristics (e.g., a scar), but not one’s knowledge and beliefs2,20.
Although most of the experimental evidence for Dualism is obtained from Western participants, non-Western participants likewise contrast minds and bodies4,5,13,14,17,21,22,23,24. This is in line with the ethnographic record, demonstrating that beliefs in the afterlife (i.e., disembodied self) and in disembodied supernatural beings (e.g., deities, spirits and ghosts) are prevalent across cultures25,26. For Western participants, however, intuitive Dualism can be especially detrimental, as it interferes with scientific literacy10,11,27, it promotes stigma (e.g., towards psychiatric patients)8,28,29 and biases judgements of criminal justice and moral responsibility30,31,32,33,34.
Why people might be Dualists, however, is unclear. One possibility is that Dualism is the product of culture—it arises entirely via learning. While learning can, no doubt, propagate Dualism, the learning account fails to explain why intuitive Dualism is so pervasive across cultures. On an alternative account, intuitive Dualism is natural for humans—it arises from two core principles that lie deep within human cognition. One such principle is intuitive physics; the other is theory of mind35.
Per intuitive physics, people consider objects as cohesive entities that can only move by immediate contact, and this knowledge manifests in early infancy36,37. For example, upon seeing one moving ball contact another (stationary) ball, infants expect the stationary ball to launch immediately. So, if the launch is delayed, infants are surprised—a response evident already in newborns38.
Theory of mind (ToM), however, leads us to attribute the actions of agents to their mental states—to their beliefs, knowledge, desires and goals39,40,41. Thus, upon seeing a person reach their hand towards a water bottle, one would spontaneously infer that the person believes there is water in the bottle, and it is this belief that caused their hand to move. This inference, however, blatantly violates intuitive physics, as it presumes that the agent’s hand (a physical object) can move spontaneously, in the absence of contact with another physical objects. And that violation of intuitive physics is bound to elicit cognitive tension. To resolve the dissonance, people might presume that mental states—the causes of the agents’ movement—aren’t physical. Thus, the tension between intuitive ToM and intuitive physics can explain how intuitive Dualism arises naturally.
The hypothesis that Dualism is natural also generates a testable prediction. If Dualism arises (in part) from ToM, then if ToM were to be attenuated, then so should intuitive Dualism35.
Recent results from autistic people bear this prediction out42. A large literature suggests that autistic people are less adept at reading the minds of others39,43,44,45,46,47,48,49,50,51,52,53. If autism attenuates ToM, and ToM begets Dualism, then in people with autism, the mind–body divide ought to be attenuated. Moreover, Dualist intuitions ought to correlate with sensitivity to ToM. This, is exactly what was found42. Still, the results from autistic individuals cannot speak to whether this attenuation of the mind–body divide is in fact caused by Dualism.
To further evaluate the origins of Dualism, and its link to ToM, here, we explore systematic gradations in ToM occurring within the neurotypical population—differences between females and males.
Numerous studies have found that males underperform females in ToM tasks. These reports obtain in both adults54,55,56,57,58,59,60,61,62 and children63,64,65,66,67,68 across dozens of languages and societies69, including a small-scale one (nomadic pastoralist63). The available findings do not establish whether this gender difference is universal or inherent to biological sex70,71. Still, one wonders whether this well-established gender difference is linked to Dualism.
If ToM is attenuated in males, and if ToM begets Dualism, then males ought to show weaker Dualism (relative to females) and instead, they ought to lean towards Physicalism (the view of body and mind as one and the same).
Experiments 1–2 explore this prediction. Experiment 1 invites participants to reason about a futuristic scenario whereby it would be possible to create a replica of one’s body; their task is to evaluate which of the donor’s traits will emerge in the replica. Experiment 2 evaluates the converse. Here, participants consider whether some psychological traits persist in the afterlife, after the demise of the body. The critical question is whether intuitions concerning embodiment vary by gender. If males lean towards Physicalism, then they ought to be more likely to consider psychological traits as embodied, hence, as more likely to emerge in the body-replica (and less likely to persist in the afterlife).
Experiment 3 explores the putative effect of Dualism on another aspect of reasoning—innateness intuitions. Past research suggests that Dualism promotes Empiricism—the belief that psychological traits cannot be innate (due to a Dualism–Essentialism interaction, discussed next)8,10,72,73. If males are less Dualist, and Dualism typically begets Empiricism, then males ought to further show weaker Empiricism (see Fig. 1). Experiment 3 examines this prediction. A final analysis evaluates whether the putative gender differences in reasoning about bodies and minds (in Experiments 1–2) are linked to ToM.
Before considering the results, two words of caution are in order. First, the hypothesized difference between males and females with respect to Dualism and Empiricism should only hold inasmuch as males and females differ systematically on their ToM abilities. Our results cannot establish whether differences in ToM arise universally, and if so, why—whether the difference is inherent to biological sex, or whether it arises from culture or other factors (e.g., linguistic ability74,75).
Second, all predictions, are relative. Thus, if males are indeed less prone to Dualism and Empiricism, such results do not imply that males are strict Physicalists (i.e., that they consider minds as indistinguishable from bodies) or Nativists. Indeed, males can certainly engage in mind reading—the small gender difference is only found relative to female. Accordingly, our question here, is whether, compared to females, males, in this sample, are less inclined towards Dualism and Empiricism, and whether these differences are linked to ToM.
Results
Body replication
In Experiment 1, participants (240 Prolific workers) were presented with a list of 80 psychological traits. Half of those traits captured actions and emotions (e.g., walking, anger)—traits that people readily anchor in the body (e.g., legs, face); the other half corresponded to knowledge and beliefs (e.g., i.e., epistemic traits)—traits that people do not readily link to any particular bodily organ (e.g., having a concept of a person; forming sentences). Their task was to indicate whether these traits would emerge in a replica of one’s body.
Since people consider epistemic traits as relatively disembodied, they should view them as less likely to emerge in the replica than emotions and action (hereafter, non-epistemic traits), in line with intuitive Dualism. Of interest is whether females should show stronger Dualism than males.
Figure 2 plots the responses. An inspection of the means suggests that, as expected, participants considered epistemic traits as less likely to emerge in the replica relative to non-epistemic traits. Critically, males considered psychological traits as more likely to emerge in the replica than females, and this difference was especially pronounced for epistemic traits.
These observations were evaluated via a generalized linear mixed effects model (response ~ trait * gender + (trait | subject) + (1 | item)), conducted over the binary trial responses (1 = will transfer to the replica; 0 = will not transfer). This model used the binomial response family in R, implemented within the glmer function of the lmer4 package76.
The significant effect of Gender (β = 0.76, SE = 0.30, Z = 2.51, p = 0.01) confirmed that males considered psychological traits as more likely to emerge in the replica than females. The significant effect of Trait (β = 0.93, SE = 0.25, Z = 3.68, p < 0.001) also showed that non-epistemic traits were considered more likely to emerge in the replica than epistemic traits. The significant interaction, however, indicated that the effect of Gender was further modulated by Trait type (β = − 0.44, SE = 0.21, Z = − 2.12, p = 0.03).
The (Gender × Trait) interaction was next interrogated by paired comparisons, controlling for the family-wise error rate using the Tukey method (implemented in the emmeans package in R). Results showed that males and females did not differ in their response to non-epistemic traits (ones that people readily anchor in the body: β = − 0.54, SE = 0.31, Z = − 1.72, p > 0.31). But when they considered epistemic traits (ones seen as ethereal), here, males were more likely to state that epistemic traits are likely to emerge in the replica (β = − 0.982, SE = 0.326, Z = − 3.01, p = 0.01). A post-hoc power analysis (conducted using the Wilcoxon-Mann–Whitney two-group test in G*power) indicated that this analysis had sufficient power to capture this contrast of interest (power = 0.889). In addition, the post-hoc tests showed that females considered non-epistemic traits as more likely to emerge than epistemic ones (β = − 1.15, SE = 0.27, Z = − 4.28, p < 0.0001), whereas for males, this difference was just marginally significant (β = − 0.712, SE = 0.28, Z = − 2.55, p = 0.052).
Altogether, these results suggest that males consider epistemic traits as more likely to emerge in a replica of one’s body than females. The selectivity of the gender-difference to epistemic traits suggests that the gender difference likely arises from males’ Physicalist stance, rather than from a simple response bias.
To further test the hypothesis that males are more likely to view the psyche as embodied, Experiment 2 invited the same participants to judge the converse, namely, whether psychological traits are likely to emerge in the afterlife (with task order counterbalanced). If males are less leaning towards Dualism (and more likely to embrace Physicalism), then now, males ought to consider psychological traits as less likely to emerge than females.
Afterlife
An inspection of the means (Fig. 3) suggests that, when people reasoned about the afterlife, males considered psychological traits as less likely to emerge (than females). The mixed effect model (described in Experiment 1) yielded a significant main effect of Gender (β = − 0.695, SE = 0.22, Z = − 3.10, p < 0.01), and the power to observe it was 0.850 (α = 0.05). The effect of Trait (β = − 0.49, SE = 0.31, Z = − 1.59, p > 0.11) and the interaction (|Z| < 1) were not significant.
Taken as a whole, Experiments 1–2 suggest that males consider epistemic psychological traits as more likely to emerge in a manipulation that preserves one’s body (i.e., body-replication), but they view (all) psychological traits as less likely to emerge upon the body’s demise, in the afterlife. The dissociation between the two tasks—depending on whether the task gauges the emergence of the psyche in the body (in the replica), or in its absence (in the afterlife)—makes it clear that the shift in response specifically concerns the perception of the psyche as embodied. The gender difference thus demonstrates that males consider the psyche as more strongly embodied than females.
To further explore the link between gender and the mind–body divide, in Experiment 3, we examine yet another consequence of Dualism, namely, innateness intuitions. If ToM begets Dualism, then males and females ought to also differ on that dimension.
Innateness intuitions
Past research has shown that people (mostly, WEIRD77 participants) are intuitive Empiricists—they believe that knowledge and beliefs are unlikely to be innate78,79. This aversion to innateness is selective—people do not simply reject all aspects of innateness. In fact, they maintain that emotions, actions, and sensations are innate73,78. It is specifically epistemic states—knowledge and beliefs—that they consider as arising strictly from experience73,78.
Taken at face value, this Empiricist stance could arise from multiple sources, including instinct blindness80, mind opacity81, and concerns with social harm82. But there is evidence that Dualism contributes to our Empiricist intuitions27,83.
Past research has shown that innateness intuitions are guided by Essentialism—the belief that living things are what they are because they possess some innate, immutable essence that resides in their bodies84,85,86. Per Dualism, however, epistemic states (e.g., knowledge, beliefs) are ethereal, distinct from the body. It thus follows that epistemic states cannot be innate27,83.
Past research has shown that innateness intuitions are indeed linked to embodiment intuitions. When presented with evidence that a psychological trait is embodied, participants are more likely to consider that trait as innate (compared to when told that the same trait has no known anchoring in the body)8,10,72.
If Dualism indeed begets Empiricism, then a reduction in Dualism ought to attenuate one’s Empiricist stance. This prediction is borne out by two pieces of evidence. First, when neurotypical participants are primed to consider bodies and minds alike (i.e., towards Physicalism), their empiricist stance declines (temporarily)10,72. The second piece of evidence comes from people with autism—a condition that is known to attenuate ToM39,43,44,45,46,47,48,49,50,51,52,53. If ToM promotes Empiricism (due to its role in Dualism), then people with ASD should be less likely to lean towards Empiricism, and instead favor Nativism (relative to neurotypical people). This is precisely what was found42.
Following this logic, one would expect gender to elicit similar effects (see Fig. 1). In particular, if (a) males show weaker ToM, (b) ToM begets Dualism, and (c) Dualism encourages Empiricism, then, not only should males (i) exhibit weaker Dualism (as shown in Experiments 1–2) but also (ii) weaker Empiricism.
To test this last prediction, Experiment 3 invited a new sample of males and females (N = 242) to reason about the innateness of psychological traits (the same traits as in Experiments 1–2). We expect males to consider psychological traits as more likely to be innate than females.
Figure 4 plots participants’ innateness intuitions. An inspection of the means suggests that, compared to females, males were more likely to consider psychological traits as innate. Additionally, epistemic traits were considered as less likely to be innate than non-epistemic traits.
In line with these observations, a mix-effect model (described in Experiment 1) yielded a significant main effect of Gender (β = 0.424, SE = 0.16, Z = 2.59, p < 0.01) and of Trait (β = 2.54, SE = 0.33, Z = 7.59, p < 0.001); the interaction (Trait × Gender) was not significant (β = 0.218, SE = 0.15, Z = 1.41, p > 0.16). The power to detect the main effect of Gender was 0.88.
To further evaluate whether people did, in fact, reject the innateness of Epistemic traits, the mean response was next compared against chance using a mixed effect model (0, in log odds; response ~ (1 | subject) + (1 | item)). Results confirmed that non-epistemic traits were rated significantly above chance (β = 1.32, SE = 0.286, Z = 4.61, p < 0.001), suggesting that people did consider these traits as innate. But when people evaluated epistemic traits, here, responses were significantly lower than chance (β = − 1.19, SE = 0.20, Z = − 5.95, p < 0.001), suggesting that people denied that epistemic traits are innate.
These results confirm that participants are indeed Empiricist—they selectively deny that knowledge and beliefs are possibly innate8,10,72,73. Males, however, are less likely to exhibit this bias than females.
Is dualism linked to ToM?
Experiments 1–3 demonstrate that males are less Dualist than females, and perhaps for this reason, they are also more likely to view psychological traits as innate. These systematic gender differences are precisely what would be predicted by the hypothesis that ToM begets Dualism, and that males’ ToM is slightly weaker than females’, in line with past research54,55,56,57,58,59,60,61,62,63,64,65,66,67,68. Still, the results discussed thus far do not address the source of the gender difference: is it linked to ToM?
To address this question, we first compared the males and females in this sample on a ToM test; we next evaluated whether ToM is linked to reasoning about bodies and minds.
In the ToM task (adapted from87), participants were presented with brief vignettes featuring a protagonist who either does or doesn’t hold a certain belief. In half of the trials, the belief was false, but the protagonist was likely to hold it (e.g., “Lisa believes Jacob is sleeping”; Lisa is likely to hold this belief as she last saw Jacob asleep on the beach, but alas, this belief is false—in reality, Jacob has since gone swimming). The other half featured true beliefs that the protagonist was unlikely to hold (e.g., “the girls believe the ice-cream in the fridge is melted”; this belief is actually true, as a power outage occurred overnight, but the girls have no reason to hold that belief, as they were meanwhile sleeping). Participants were asked to quickly evaluate whether or not the protagonist holds this belief. Sensitivity to ToM was gauged by response accuracy speed. This analysis was applied to the entire sample of Experiments 1–2 (excluding one non-binary participant and one inattentive participant whose mean response accuracy on the ToM test was 0.05; N = 238).
Results (Fig. 5A) showed that, compared to females, males in this sample indeed had greater difficulty reasoning about the minds of others, as their accuracy was significantly lower (β = − 0.33, SE = 0.16, Z = − 2.03, p = 0.04), and their response time was higher (t(236) = 1.97, p = 0.05)
To determine whether ToM performance is linked to reasoning about minds and bodies, we next assessed participants’ Dualist stance by computing their “Dualism score”—their tendency to consider epistemic traits as more likely to emerge in the afterlife, and less likely to emerge in the replication task (∆(epistemic-nonepistemic)Afterlife + ∆(nonepistemic-epistemic)Replication). This analysis excluded the outliers on the Dualism tasks (as described in Experiments 1–2).
Dualism scores were next correlated with ToM performance in Experiments in 1–2 (where Dualism was assessed). The correlation between Dualism and ToM accuracy was significant (r(215) = 0.24, p < 0.001 see Fig. 5b): the better were participants able to reason about the minds of others (i.e., higher ToM accuracy) the more Dualist they were (i.e., larger Dualism scores). These results suggest that reasoning about bodies-and minds is linked to the ability to reason about the minds of others.
Discussion
People tend to consider the mind as ethereal, distinct from the body. This intuitive Dualist stance has been demonstrated in adults and children, in Western and non-Western participants1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16,17,18,20,21,22,23,24,88,89, and its consequences on reasoning are widespread8,10,11,27,28,29,30,31,32,33,34.
Why people are putative Dualists, however, is unclear. In particular, one wonders whether Dualism arises only by cultural transmission, or whether the illusion of the mind–body divide can also emerge naturally, from ToM35.
To address this question, here, we investigated whether individual differences in ToM capacities, occurring within the neurotypical population—between males and females54,55,56,57,58,59,60,61,62,63,64,65,66,67,68,69—are linked to Dualism. Experiments 1–2 show that this is indeed the case.
Males, in this sample, considered the psyche as more strongly embodied than females: they believed that epistemic states are more likely to emerge in a replica of one’s body (in Experiment 1) and that psychological traits are less likely to persist upon the body’s demise, in the afterlife (in Experiment 2). Experiment 3 further showed that males are also more likely to consider psychological traits as innate—this is expected by past findings, suggesting that Dualism begets Empiricism8,10,72,73.
A follow-up analysis has confirmed that these differences in reasoning about bodies and minds are linked to ToM. Not only did males in this sample score lower than females on ToM, but their ToM scores correlated with their Dualist intuitions.
As noted, these results ought to be interpreted with caution, as the gender differences observed here may not hold universally, and it certainly does not speak to the reasoning of any individual person. And indeed, ToM abilities demonstrably depend on multiple factors, including linguistic experience74,75 and culture90,91. But inasmuch as females show superior ToM, they ought to lean towards Dualism and Empiricism. Dualism, then, is linked to ToM.
Whether ToM in fact promotes Dualism is more difficult to determine. Still, the present findings (from neurotypical males and females) complement past research from autistic individuals42. In both cases, lower ToM performance (in males, and in people with ASD) is linked to weaker Dualism and stronger Nativism (relative to females and the NT population, respectively). This association (between ToM and Dualism) falls short of establishing causation. Nonetheless, the convergence between the two sets of findings—from neurotypical and autistic people—is striking. This outcome is in line with the hypothesis that ToM begets Dualism. The illusion of the mind–body divide, then, may not be solely a cultural construct. Rather, Dualism might be grounded in a core psychological mechanism that lies deep within the human mind.
Dualism is further significant because it demonstrably stands in the way of scientific literacy and the understanding of public health. Specifically, Dualism promotes false beliefs about neuroscience and innateness10,11,27, it engenders misconceptions about psychiatric disorders8,28,29, and meddles with reasoning about moral responsibility and criminal justice30,31,32,33,34. Understanding the origins of Dualism may help combat its many tolls on reasoning and shed light on human nature.
Methods
Experiments 1–2 (replication/afterlife)
Participants
Participants were 240 Prolific workers. They were native English speakers, neurotypical, with no known diagnosis of language- reading disorders or ASD. Each experiment recruited an equal number of males and females; one participant self-identified as non-binary was excluded from the analysis (for participants’ demographics and country of origin, see Figs. S1-2). Sample size was informed by pilot work, suggesting that the selected sample size is sufficient to attain a power of 0.8 at the 0.05 alpha level.
Data exclusion
The analyses of Experiments 1–2 excluded participants whose mean response fell 2 SD beyond the cell mean. This procedure removed 15 participants from Experiment 1 (6 females; one additional participant, identified as nonbinary, was likewise excluded); and 9 participants (all females) from Experiment 2. An analysis of the entire sample yielded similar conclusions.
Materials and tasks
Participants took part in four tasks. First, participants were given the two “Dualism” tasks—body replication and afterlife (counterbalanced for order). Next, they were administered the theory of mind task. Finally, participants were given the autism Quotient task.
The Dualism tasks featured a list of 80 psychological traits (from10,78). Half of those traits captured knowledge and beliefs—hereafter, “epistemic traits” (e.g., having a concept of a person); the other half correspond to actions and emotions (e.g., squatting, fear), hereafter, non-epistemic traits. These traits were arranged in two counterbalanced lists. Each participant performed each task with a different item list, such that, across participants, all traits were presented equally in both tasks, and within each task, each trait only appeared once.
In Experiment 1, participants were invited to suppose it was possible to grow a replica of the body of an adult human donor. The replica preserves every aspect of the human body and brain. With this in mind, participants were asked to determine whether a given trait would likely emerge in the replica. In Experiment 2, participants were invited to judge whether each trait is likely to persist in the afterlife. For the full list of materials and instructions in Experiments 1–2 see SM, Appendices I–II.
After the two Dualism probes, participants were given the ToM task. In the ToM test (adapted from87), participants were randomly presented with 20 short vignettes. Each vignette features a protagonist who either does or does not hold a certain belief. The belief, in turn, was either true or false. In so doing, we sought to dissociate the presence of true/false belief with its veracity. Thus, in half of the vignettes, the belief was false, and the protagonist was likely to hold that belief (under the circumstances detailed in the vignette), whereas in the others, the belief was true, but the protagonist was unlikely to hold it. Participants were instructed to quickly determine whether the probe sentence was true or false (for the full materials and instructions, see SM, Appendix III).
Finally, participants were given the AQ (from55; this test asks participants to respond to fifty short sentences, related to their social skills, attention switching, attention to detail, communication, and imagination.
Experiment 3 (Innateness intuitions)
Participants
Experiment 3 was administered to 242 participants. Of those, 120 were Prolific workers (60 males); the remaining 122 participants with students and the department of Psychology at Northeastern University who took part in the experiment for course credit. Because the population of Psychology students at Northeastern is heavily female-dominated, most Northeastern participants were females (N = 94). Sample size was set to match Experiments 1–2 (for participants’ demographics and country of origin, see Figs. S1–2).
Data exclusion
As in previous experiments, the analysis of Experiment 3 excluded participants whose mean response fell 2 SD beyond the mean. 21 participants (16 females) were excluded from Experiment 3. An analysis of the entire sample yielded similar conclusions.
Materials
All participants took part in three tasks. First, participants performed the “innateness” task, next they performed the ToM task, and finally the AQ evaluation. The subset of Psychology students also took part in the two Dualism tasks (as in Experiments 1–2), administered prior to the Innateness task.
The innateness task featured the same list of 80 psychological traits from Experiments 1–2 (with order randomized). These items were designed to capture characteristics that are likely to hold across cultures; epistemic traits, specifically, were selected from a list of traits that have been widely documented in small scale societies (adapted from the Appendix in82).
Participants evaluated whether these traits are inborn in humans. Participants were told that “inborn traits are ones that develop in humans spontaneously. Some of these traits (e.g., having five fingers) are present at birth, but others (e.g., facial hair in men) can appear later in development. All inborn traits, however, emerge in the typical course of development, even if an individual has never had the opportunity to witness these behaviors in other people”. Participants were asked to give a binary response as to whether each trait is inborn in humans. The full lists of materials are presented in the SM, Appendix I–II.
All materials and procedures were reviewed and approved by the Institutional Review Board at Northeastern University; all methods were performed in accordance with those guidelines and regulations. An informed consent form was obtained from all participants or their parents/legal guardians.
Data availability
All data are made available in the SM file, attached.
References
Bloom, P. Generativity within language and other cognitive domains. Cognition 51, 177–189 (1994).
Forstmann, M. & Burgmer, P. Adults are intuitive mind-body dualists. J. Exp. Psychol. Gen. 144, 222–235. https://doi.org/10.1037/xge0000045 (2015).
Bering, J., McLeod, K. & Shackelford, T. Reasoning about dead agents reveals possible adaptive trends. Hum. Nat. 16, 360–381. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12110-005-1015-2 (2005).
Cohen, E. & Barrett, J. When minds migrate: Conceptualizing spirit possession. J. Cogn. Cult. 8, 23–48. https://doi.org/10.1163/156770908X289198 (2008).
Cohen, E., Burdett, E., Knight, N. & Barrett, J. Cross-cultural similarities and differences in person-body reasoning: Experimental evidence from the United Kingdom and Brazilian Amazon. Cogn. Sci. 35, 1282–1304. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1551-6709.2011.01172.x (2011).
Forstmann, M., Burgmer, P. & Mussweiler, T. “The mind is willing, but the flesh is weak”: The effects of mind-body dualism on health behavior. Psychol. Sci. 23, 1239–1245. https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797612442392 (2012).
Heflick, N. A., Goldenberg, J. L., Hart, J. & Kamp, S. M. Death awareness and body–self dualism: A why and how of afterlife belief. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. 45, 267–275. https://doi.org/10.1002/ejsp.2075 (2015).
Berent, I. & Platt, M. Laypeople’s misconceptions towards psychiatric disorders: Brain disorders are presumed innate. Cogn. Sci. 45, e12970 (2021).
Berent, I. & Platt, M. The true “me”—Mind or body?. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 93, 104100 (2021).
Berent, I., Platt, M. & Sandoboe, G. M. In Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy, Ch. 5 Vol. 4 (eds Lombrozo, T. et al.) 112–154 (Oxford University Press, 2021).
Sandoboe, G. & Berent, I. The seductive allure of the brain: Dualism and lay perceptions of neuroscience. Cogn. Neuropsychol. 38, 205–230 (2021).
Berent, I. Can the mind command the body?. Cogn. Sci. 45, e13067 (2021).
Slingerland, E. & Chudek, M. The prevalence of mind-body dualism in early China. Cogn. Sci. 35, 997. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1551-6709.2011.01186.x (2011).
Chudek, M., McNamara, R. A., Birch, S., Bloom, P. & Henrich, J. Do minds switch bodies? Dualist interpretations across ages and societies. Relig. Brain Behav. 8, 354–368. https://doi.org/10.1080/2153599X.2017.1377757 (2018).
Stanovich, K. E. Implicit philosophies of mind: The dualism scale and its relation to religiosity and belief in extrasensory perception. J. Psychol. 123, 5–23. https://doi.org/10.1080/00223980.1989.10542958 (1989).
Weisman, K., Dweck, C. S. & Markman, E. M. Rethinking people’s conceptions of mental life. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 114, 11374–11379. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1704347114 (2017).
Weisman, K. et al. Similarities and differences in concepts of mental life among adults and children in five cultures. Nat. Hum. Behav. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-021-01184-8 (2021).
Bering, J. M. & Bjorklund, D. F. The natural emergence of reasoning about the afterlife as a developmental regularity. Dev. Psychol. 40, 217–233. https://doi.org/10.1037/0012-1649.40.2.217 (2004).
Bering, J. M. Intuitive conceptions of dead agents’ minds: The natural foundations of afterlife beliefs as phenomenological boundary. J. Cogn. Cult. 2, 263–308. https://doi.org/10.1163/15685370260441008 (2002).
Hood, B., Gjersoe, N. L. & Bloom, P. Do children think that duplicating the body also duplicates the mind?. Cognition 125, 466–474. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2012.07.005 (2012).
Boyer, P. Minds Make Societies: How Cognition Explains the World Humans Create (Yale University Press, 2018).
Watson-Jones, R. E., Busch, J. T. A., Harris, P. L. & Legare, C. H. Does the body survive death? Cultural variation in beliefs about life everlasting. Cogn. Sci. 41, 455–476. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12430 (2017).
Lane, J. D., Zhu, L., Evans, E. M. & Wellman, H. M. Developing concepts of the mind, body, and afterlife: Exploring the roles of narrative context and culture. J. Cogn. Cult. 16, 50–82. https://doi.org/10.1163/15685373-12342168 (2016).
Astuti, R. & Harris, P. L. Understanding mortality and the life of the ancestors in rural Madagascar. Cogn. Sci. 32, 713–740. https://doi.org/10.1080/03640210802066907 (2008).
Boyer, P. Minds Make Societies: How Cognition Explains the World Humans Create (Yale University Press, 2018).
Lomnitz-Adler, C. Death and the Idea of Mexico (Zone Books, 2005).
Berent, I. Can we get human nature right?. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 118, e2108274118 (2021).
Valtonen, J., Ahn, W.-K. & Cimpian, A. Neurodualism: People assume that the brain affects the mind more than the mind affects the brain. Brain Cogn. Sci. 45, e13034. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.13034 (2021).
Ahn, W.-K., Kim, N. S. & Lebowitz, M. S. In Oxford Library of Psychology. The Oxford Handbook of Causal Reasoning (ed. Michael Waldmann, R.) 603–617 (Oxford University Press, 2017).
Monterosso, J., Royzman, E. B. & Schwartz, B. Explaining away responsibility: Effects of scientific explanation on perceived culpability. Ethics Behav. 15, 139–158. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb1502_4 (2005).
Heath, W. P., Stone, J., Darley, J. M. & Grannemann, B. D. Yes, I did it, but don’t blame me: Perceptions of excuse defenses. J. Psychiatry Law 31, 187–226. https://doi.org/10.1177/009318530303100204 (2003).
Aspinwall, L. G., Brown, T. R. & Tabery, J. The double-edged sword: Does biomechanism increase or decrease judges’ sentencing of psychopaths?. Science (New York, N.Y.) 337, 846. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1219569 (2012).
Gurley, J. R. & Marcus, D. K. The effects of neuroimaging and brain injury on insanity defenses. Behav. Sci. Law 26, 85–97. https://doi.org/10.1002/bsl.797 (2008).
Greene, J. & Cohen, J. For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything. Philos. Trans. Biol. Sci. 359, 1775–1785. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2004.1546 (2004).
Bloom, P. Descartes’ Baby: How the Science of Child Development Explains What Makes us Human (Basic Books, 2004).
Spelke, E. S. Initial knowledge: Six suggestions. Cognition 50, 431–445 (1994).
Spelke, E. S., Breinlinger, K., Macomber, J. & Jacobson, K. Origins of knowledge. Psychol. Rev. 99, 605–632. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.99.4.605 (1992).
Mascalzoni, E., Regolin, L., Vallortigara, G. & Simion, F. The cradle of causal reasoning: Newborns’ preference for physical causality. Dev. Sci. 16, 327–335. https://doi.org/10.1111/desc.12018 (2013).
Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A. M. & Frith, U. Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”?. Cognition 21, 37–46. https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(85)90022-8 (1985).
Leslie, A. M. Pretense and representation: The origins of ‘theory of mind’. Psychol. Rev. 94, 412–426 (1987).
Leslie, A. M., Friedman, O. & German, T. P. Core mechanisms in “theory of mind”. Trends Cogn. Sci. 8, 528–533 (2004).
Berent, I., Theodore, R. & Valencia, E. Autism attenuates the perception of the mind-body divide. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 119, e2211628119 (2022).
Baron-Cohen, S. et al. The “reading the mind in the eyes” test: Complete absence of typical sex difference in ~400 men and women with autism. PLoS One 10, e0136521. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0136521 (2015).
Senju, A., Southgate, V., White, S. & Frith, U. Mindblind eyes: An absence of spontaneous theory of mind in Asperger syndrome. Science 325, 883–885. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1176170 (2009).
Atherton, G. & Cross, L. Animal faux pas: Two legs good four legs bad for theory of mind, but not in the broad autism spectrum. J. Genet. Psychol. 180, 81–95. https://doi.org/10.1080/00221325.2019.1593100 (2019).
Thiébaut, F. I. et al. Does faux pas detection in adult autism reflect differences in social cognition or decision-making abilities?. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 46, 103–112. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10803-015-2551-1 (2016).
Zalla, T., Sav, A.-M., Stopin, A., Ahade, S. & Leboyer, M. Faux pas detection and intentional action in Asperger Syndrome. A replication on a French sample. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 39, 373–382. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10803-008-0634-y (2009).
Buon, M. et al. The role of causal and intentional judgments in moral reasoning in individuals with high functioning autism. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 43, 458–470. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10803-012-1588-7 (2012).
Moran, J. M. et al. Impaired theory of mind for moral judgment in high-functioning autism. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 108, 2688–2692. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1011734108 (2011).
Rogé, B. & Mullet, E. Blame and forgiveness judgements among children, adolescents and adults with autism. Autism 15, 702–712. https://doi.org/10.1177/1362361310394219 (2011).
Jameel, L., Vyas, K., Bellesi, G., Crawford, S. & Channon, S. Thinking about other’s mistakes: Contrasting patterns of performance in groups high or low in autistic or psychopathic traits. Cogn. Neuropsychiatry 24, 369–385. https://doi.org/10.1080/13546805.2019.1667317 (2019).
Bellesi, G., Vyas, K., Jameel, L. & Channon, S. Moral reasoning about everyday situations in adults with autism spectrum disorder. Res. Autism Spectr. Disord. 52, 1–11. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.rasd.2018.04.009 (2018).
Frith, U. Emanuel Miller lecture: Confusions and controversies about Asperger syndrome. J. Child Psychol. Psychiatry 45, 672–686. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1469-7610.2004.00262.x (2004).
Kirkland, R. A., Peterson, E., Baker, C. A., Miller, S. & Pulos, S. Meta-analysis reveals adult female superiority in “Reading the Mind in the Eyes Test”. N. Am. J. Psychol. 15, 121 (2013).
Baron-Cohen, S., Wheelwright, S., Skinner, R., Martin, J. & Clubley, E. The Autism-Spectrum Quotient (AQ): Evidence from Asperger syndrome/high-functioning autism, males and females, scientists and mathematicians. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 31, 5–17 (2001).
Adenzato, M. et al. Gender differences in cognitive Theory of Mind revealed by transcranial direct current stimulation on medial prefrontal cortex. Sci. Rep. 7, 41219. https://doi.org/10.1038/srep41219 (2017).
Dorris, L., Young, D., Byrne, K. & Hoyle, R. Cognitive empathy across the lifespan. Dev. Med. Child Neurol. https://doi.org/10.1111/dmcn.15263 (2022).
Groen, Y., Fuermaier, A. B. M., Den Heijer, A. E., Tucha, O. & Althaus, M. The Empathy and Systemizing Quotient: The psychometric properties of the Dutch version and a review of the cross-cultural stability. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 45, 2848–2864. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10803-015-2448-z (2015).
Khorashad, B. S. et al. The “Reading the Mind in the Eyes” test: Investigation of psychometric properties and test-retest reliability of the Persian version. J. Autism Dev. Disord. 45, 2651–2666. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10803-015-2427-4 (2015).
Vellante, M. et al. The “Reading the Mind in the Eyes” test: Systematic review of psychometric properties and a validation study in Italy. Cogn. Neuropsychiatry 18, 326–354. https://doi.org/10.1080/13546805.2012.721728 (2013).
Hünefeldt, T., Hussein, O. & Olivetti Belardinelli, M. Cross-cultural differences in intercultural mindreading: Evidence from a sample of Palestinian, Italian, and German adolescents. PsyCh J. 10, 263–274. https://doi.org/10.1002/pchj.417 (2021).
Quesque, F. et al. Does culture shape our understanding of others’ thoughts and emotions? An investigation across 12 countries. Neuropsychology 36, 664–682. https://doi.org/10.1037/neu0000817 (2022).
Ghrear, S., Chudek, M., Fung, K., Mathew, S. & Birch, S. A. J. Cultural variations in the curse of knowledge: The curse of knowledge bias in children from a nomadic pastoralist culture in Kenya. J. Cogn. Cult. 19, 366–384. https://doi.org/10.1163/15685373-12340064 (2019).
Cassetta, B. D., Pexman, P. M. & Goghari, V. M. Cognitive and affective theory of mind and relations with executive functioning in middle childhood. Merrill-Palmer Q. 64, 514–538 (2018).
Wang, S. et al. A cross-cultural study of theory of mind using strange stories in school-aged children from Australia and mainland China. J. Cogn. Dev. https://doi.org/10.1080/15248372.2021.1974445 (2021).
Sundqvist, A., Holmer, E., Koch, F. S. & Heimann, M. Developing theory of mind abilities in Swedish pre-schoolers. Infant Child Dev. 27, 1–14. https://doi.org/10.1002/icd.2090 (2018).
Thompson, R. B. & Thornton, B. Gender and theory of mind in preschoolers’ group effort: Evidence for timing differences behind children’s earliest social loafing. J. Soc. Psychol. 154, 475–479. https://doi.org/10.1080/00224545.2014.933763 (2014).
Calero, C. I., Salles, A., Semelman, M. & Sigman, M. Age and gender dependent development of Theory of Mind in 6- to 8-years old children. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 7, 281. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00281 (2013).
Greenberg, D. M. et al. Sex and age differences in “theory of mind” across 57 countries using the English version of the “Reading the Mind in the Eyes” Test. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 120, e2022385119. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2022385119 (2023).
Knickmeyer, R. C. & Baron-Cohen, S. Fetal testosterone and sex differences in typical social development and in autism. J. Child Neurol. 21, 825–845. https://doi.org/10.1177/08830738060210101601 (2006).
Hönekopp, J. Digit ratio 2D:4D in relation to autism spectrum disorders, empathizing, and systemizing: A quantitative review. Autism Res. 5, 221–230. https://doi.org/10.1002/aur.1230 (2012).
Berent, I. & Platt, M. Public misconceptions about dyslexia: The role of intuitive psychology. PLoS One 16(2), e0259019 (2021).
Berent, I., Barrett, L. F. & Platt, M. Essentialist biases in reasoning about emotions. Front. Psychol. Cogn. Sci. 11, 562666. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.562666 (2020).
Richardson, H. et al. Reduced neural selectivity for mental states in deaf children with delayed exposure to sign language. Nat. Commun. 11, 3246. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-020-17004-y (2020).
Pyers, J. E. & Senghas, A. Language promotes false-belief understanding: Evidence from learners of a new sign language. Psychol. Sci. 20, 805–812 (2009).
Bates, D., Mächler, M., Bolker, B. & Walker, S. Fitting linear mixed-effects models using {lme4}. J. Stat. Softw. 67, 1–48. https://doi.org/10.18637/jss.v067.i01 (2015).
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J. & Norenzayan, A. The weirdest people in the world?. Behav. Brain Sci. 33, 61–83. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X0999152X (2010).
Berent, I., Platt, M. & Sandoboe, G. M. People’s intuitions about innateness. Open Mind Discov. Cogn. Sci. 3, 101–114 (2019).
Wang, J. J. & Feigenson, L. Is empiricism innate? Preference for nurture over nature in people’s beliefs about the origins of human knowledge. Open Mind 3, 89–100 (2019).
Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. Beyond intuition and instinct blindness: Toward an evolutionarily rigorous cognitive science. Cognition 50, 41–77. https://doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(94)90020-5 (1994).
Carruthers, P. How mindreading might mislead cognitive science. J. Conscious. Stud. 27, 195–219 (2020).
Pinker, S. The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature (Viking, 2002).
Berent, I. The Blind Storyteller: How We Reason About Human Nature (Oxford University Press, 2020).
Berent, I. On the matter of essence. Cognition 213, 104701 (2021).
Newman, G. E. & Keil, F. C. Where is the essence? Developmental shifts in children’s beliefs about internal features. Child Dev. 79, 1344–1356. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8624.2008.01192.x (2008).
Lindquist, K. A., Gendron, M., Oosterwijk, S. & Barrett, L. F. Do people essentialize emotions? Individual differences in emotion essentialism and emotional experience. Emotion (Washington, D.C.) 13, 629–644. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0032283 (2013).
Dodell-Feder, D., Koster-Hale, J., Bedny, M. & Saxe, R. fMRI item analysis in a theory of mind task. Neuroimage 55, 705–712. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuroimage.2010.12.040 (2011).
Bering, J. M., Blasi, C. H. & Bjorklund, D. F. The development of “afterlife” beliefs in religiously and secularly schooled children. Br. J. Dev. Psychol. 23, 587–607. https://doi.org/10.1348/026151005X36498 (2005).
Harris, P. L. & Giménez, M. Children’s acceptance of conflicting testimony: The case of death. J. Cogn. Cult. 5, 143–164. https://doi.org/10.1163/1568537054068606 (2005).
McNamara, R. A., Willard, A. K., Norenzayan, A. & Henrich, J. Weighing outcome vs. intent across societies: How cultural models of mind shape moral reasoning. Cognition 182, 95–108. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2018.09.008 (2019).
Barrett, H. C. & Saxe, R. R. Are some cultures more mind-minded in their moral judgements than others?. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. B Biol. Sci. 376, 20200288. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2020.0288 (2021).
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
I.B. conceived the project, designed and conducted the experiments, analyzed the data and wrote the manuscript.
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Competing interests
The author declares no competing interests.
Additional information
Publisher's note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Supplementary Information
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
About this article
Cite this article
Berent, I. The illusion of the mind–body divide is attenuated in males. Sci Rep 13, 6653 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-023-33079-1
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-023-33079-1
Comments
By submitting a comment you agree to abide by our Terms and Community Guidelines. If you find something abusive or that does not comply with our terms or guidelines please flag it as inappropriate.