Abstract
According to the classic theory of life history evolution, ageing evolves because selection on traits necessarily weakens throughout reproductive life. But this inexorable decline of the selection force with adult age was shown to crucially depend on specific assumptions that are not necessarily fulfilled. Whether ageing still evolves upon their relaxation remains an open problem. Here, we propose a fully dynamical model of life history evolution that does not presuppose any specific pattern the force of selection should follow. The model shows: (i) ageing can stably evolve, but negative ageing cannot; (ii) when ageing is a stable equilibrium, the associated selection force decreases with reproductive age; (iii) non-decreasing selection is either a transient or an unstable phenomenon. Thus, we generalize the classic theory of the evolution of ageing while overturning its logic: the decline of selection with age evolves dynamically, and is not an implicit consequence of certain assumptions.
Similar content being viewed by others
Introduction
Ageing is a degeneration in the physiological state of adult individuals that progressively curbs their fecundity and survival as their age increases1,2. Ageing is observed in a great number of species3,4,5. Why does ageing evolve? Established theories1,6,7,8,9 state that this is because the force of selection suffers an inexorable decline with adult age. Accordingly, the fitness value of reproduction and survival late in life is discounted by a combination of two factors. One is the inherent improbability, from the point of view of a newborn, of reaching late ages when compared to any earlier age. The other factor is a dilution effect on late reproduction, should the population be growing in size. Therefore, the likelihood of detrimental mutations, with or without earlier pleiotropic benefits, to spread and persist in the population would increase the later their age of action. Ageing would be the phenotypic manifestation of such mutations.
The pillar of this established view was undermined by what has been deemed as one of the major insights in the field over the last 35 years: the force of selection may not necessarily decline with adult age10. In particular, Baudisch put Hamilton’s model8, recognized as the most mathematically explicit version of the classic theory1,11,12, under scrutiny. This revealed that a necessary decline in the selection force with age only derives from the restrictive assumptions that, when mutations act at each age separately, they do so via small additive changes in fecundity and small proportional changes in survival10,13,14. Under alternative and equally plausible assumptions about the working of age-specific mutations, the selection force was shown to increase with age in some cases13. For example, reversing the assumptions of the classic theory, small proportional changes in fecundity and small additive changes in survival can lead to increasing selection over some ages (Fig. 1). In other words, Baudisch’s work showed that the classic theory implicitly assumed an inexorably declining selection force with age rather than deriving it from general principles. To what extent this revelation undermines the validity of the classic theory remains unclear. This is the starting point of the present work. Our goal is an in-depth exploration of the consequences of possibly non-declining selection with age on life history evolution.
The strength of selection on fecundity and survival at a given age depends on the whole life history15,16, i.e., on the complete age trajectories of fecundity and survival. The age-specific selection force then typically changes as the life history evolves. The classic theory, however, identifies a pattern to this force that is invariant to evolutionary change. Under specific assumptions about how mutations alter fecundity and survival, there is a persistent decline in a selection over adult ages that is independent of the schedules of fecundity and survival8. Ecological factors, like predators and environmental hazards, that impact population density can modify selective forces that mold the life history6,17,18,19. But these factors can at most modulate, and not counter, the decline of selection with adult age. The exact quantification of age-specific fecundity and survival, as well as of the corresponding selective forces and their change during evolution, is then irrelevant to the conclusion of the classic theory that ageing is evolutionary inevitable. The invariant bias of selection against late-life alone implies this conclusion.
However, once we relax the assumptions of the classic theory, selection may not decline with reproductive age. And there no longer is an invariant pattern to the selection force that we can leverage. Any inference about the evolutionary inevitability of ageing is then unwarranted. The following questions naturally emerge: Can selection that increases with age persist with time? Can this lead to the evolution of increasing fecundity and survival with age (negative ageing)? Do the initial conditions, i.e., the ancestral life history, matter to the outcome of the evolutionary process? To answer these questions, we should keep track of the evolutionary dynamics of fecundity and survival at each age, i.e., how they change with time in response to current selection on them, and predict the long-run tendencies of these dynamics. Here, we propose and analyse a dynamic model that does just that. At the heart of our model is the breeder’s equation from quantitative genetics20. We simplify this equation by assuming small additive genetic variance equal for all traits and no covariances between traits at all times. The model can accommodate all sorts of genetic effects beyond additive and proportional effects. But we continue to assume effects limited to single ages. In this way, the selection force is not constrained to decline with age. The model also includes a mechanism of density dependence to keep population size constant. The evolution of fecundity and the evolution of survival are studied separately.
Results
Our model enables us to give a dynamical meaning to the notion of ‘inevitability’ that is often evoked with reference to the evolution of ageing8. Ageing, a progressive decline in fecundity and survival with reproductive age, is the only stable outcome of life history evolution under age-specific genetic variation, i.e. with effects at single ages. This is so even if such variation modifies fecundity and survival in ways that may lead to increasing selection over reproductive ages and largely irrespective of the ancestral life history from which the evolutionary process is initiated. An ageless life history, where fecundity and survival remain constant with age throughout the reproductive period, cannot be an equilibrium. Unexpectedly, negative ageing may be an equilibrium, but it is unstable. More generally, the absence of ageing is a transient or unstable state. The selection forces on fecundity and survival at reproductive ages may not always show a pattern of persistent decline during evolution. But, again, this is a transient or unstable phenomenon. When evolutionary dynamics reach a stable resting state and, therefore, ageing has evolved, equilibrium selective forces must display a pattern of persistent decline with age. Results that are specific to fecundity evolution or to survival evolution are reported hereafter.
Fecundity
Under broad conditions, if an equilibrium exists, it is unique. Depending on the exact form of genetic effects, this equilibrium can take two forms. Starting from the age of first reproduction, either fecundity decreases with each successive age or fecundity increases with each successive age. In the former case (ageing), the equilibrium is attractive and stable, while in the latter case (negative ageing) the equilibrium is unstable and everywhere repelling (Fig. 2).
Survival
Life histories for which survival at each reproductive age is greater than survival at any later age (ageing) form a globally attractive set for evolutionary dynamics. Life histories for which survival increases with each reproductive age (negative ageing) instead form a set that these dynamics repel. Depending on the form of genetic effects, equilibrium survival may be found inside one or the other set. The existence and number of equilibria, as well as exact dynamics near them, remain unknown (Fig. 3). An analysis of a simplified model molded after21 with only two age classes (Supplementary Methods) reveals that there may be more than one equilibrium at which survival displays a decline with age. Proportional effects on survival, as assumed by the classic theory, do not lead to an equilibrium in our model.
Discussion
In our model, ageing is evolutionarily inevitable in a dynamical sense irrespective of the genetics of fecundity and survival. Selective forces may at times be stronger in late life than in earlier life. But, as we show, this property pertains to either a transient or an unstable state, which is eventually abandoned. An ever-declining force with age is not an intrinsic property of selection and the one driver behind the evolution of ageing, as the classic theory8 implicitly assumes13. Instead, a persistent, age-related weakening of selective forces is itself a result of evolution. Our model may then be viewed as a generalization of the classic theory where an implicit assumption of the latter is turned into a prediction.
In this generalization process, some assumptions of the classic theory (type of genetic effects) are relaxed, while others are kept. An aspect of relevance is that our model, like the classic theory, presupposes genetic variation with effects that are limited to single ages. From the theoretical standpoint, the assumption of age-specific effects has found both critics9,22,23,24 and supporters25,26. The experimental literature appears to be equally mixed27. While one study did not find evidence of age-specific effects28, another study found evidence that these effects exist, yet not at all ages29. More recently, age-specific mutational effects with influence on fecundity were detected30,31. Research on model organisms shows how a single mutation may modify the organism’s entire survival profile32. This fact alone, however, does not preclude the existence of age-specific mutations with an effect on survival. Overall, more experiments are needed to understand the age scope of mutations33,34. Importantly, effects on survival lasting indefinitely after the age of onset avoid the possibility that selection may increase with age35.
However, age-specificity remains an important component of the most advanced developments of the mutation-accumulation hypothesis of ageing25,26. The newest models of this hypothesis have overcome previous linearity assumptions in dealing with epistatic interactions among mutations36. These models are sufficiently powerful to allow computation of, among other things, the equilibrium distribution, when it exists, of mortality over age in a genetically and, therefore, demographically heterogeneous population under mutation-selection balance25,26. Some equilibrium results of these models can explain features of observed mortality, i.e., its deceleration at very late ages37, that are not within the reach of the classic theory. They also yield predictions, i.e., extremal mortality before the last reproductive age, that even contradict this theory. Despite sharing both an assumption of age-specificity and a dynamical perspective, a direct comparison of our work with these models appears arduous because of other, diverging assumptions in the overall approach. The architecture of advanced models of mutation-accumulation is very general38. They are genetically detailed in the haploid case. They can in principle accommodate both beneficial mutations and detrimental ones as well as effects that may be pleiotropic to some degree, i.e., of different sign at different ages, or not only additive. But analysis of these models appears to be mostly focused on the case of detrimental, age-specific mutations with additive effects on mortality. The aim is to compute the load of such mutations that a population can tolerate. Our model, instead, is not genetically explicit and tracks life history evolution at the phenotypic level. Selection only acts on beneficial variation with a typically non-additive effect on fecundity and mortality. Moreover, our analysis in this work is mostly qualitative. The focus is on the ultimate age pattern of fecundity and survival and their selection gradients, i.e., whether they increase, decline, or stay constant with age. We are not interested in the exact shape of these trajectories at equilibrium, although some of these may be computed with our methods (Supplementary Methods).
Our broadly qualitative look at age patterns and our presupposition of a perennial tendency to fitness increase are also behind our assumption, only alluded to in the classic theory7,8, of density dependence. On the one hand, any model with a long-term view like ours should include a mechanism to keep population size in check. Otherwise, the fixation of beneficial variants would eventually make population growth unsustainable. On the other hand, the still ongoing debate on the role of density dependence in the presence of extrinsic mortality6,17,18,19,35 shows that the exact form of density dependence a population experiences may matter to the evolution of ageing. Of those forms the debate has considered (our age-independent decrements in fecundity or survival being one of them), some may modulate the rate of ageing, i.e., how fast fecundity and survival decline with reproductive age. Therefore, we cannot exclude that the shape of equilibrium fecundity and survival schedules for our model may bear the signature of the assumed form of density dependence. But this issue is out of the scope of the present work. Here, we are concerned with the extent to which the conclusions of the classic theory hold in the face of genetic effects that can lead to increasing selection with age. However, when these effects are proportional, i.e., the classical assumption, they act on survival in the same way as our chosen mechanism of density dependence. This may be the reason that the classic theory has no equilibrium in our model.
A potential limitation of our results comes from our usage of the breeder’s equation. With a constant variance-covariance structure among traits, the accuracy of this equation best approximates short-term evolutionary change only39. This is because the whole trait distributions are not tracked as they change along with the variability upon which selection acts. In this respect, we should remark again that our dynamical analysis is qualitative in nature, as we are interested in whether life histories have a tendency to evolve ageing or not. We do not expect accurate, long-term predictions of equilibrium fecundity and survival at each age from our recursion of the breeder’s equation. Obtaining the overall directions of life history evolution suffice. Moreover, our local stability analysis of equilibria should not be affected by the long-term inaccuracies that are inherent to the breeder’s equation.
The evolution of the variance-covariance structure among traits, i.e., the G matrix for a finite number of traits, is a major research topic that has proven hard to deal with analytically40. For our purposes, assuming such structure to be constant with no covariances and small variances for each trait is needed for analytical tractability. This is also an assumption of the classic theory. Including a nontrivial, time-dependent covariance structure in our model may thus modify our findings—but such an approach would likely come with substantial analytical challenges.
However, our results are still indirectly suggestive of what the role may be of the trade-offs that determine those trait covariances—and which we have excluded from our model. Looking across the tree of life, trajectories of fecundity and survival over adulthood are very diverse from one species to another5. Ageing is only one of the many patterns that these trajectories can follow. It has been argued23 that the inability of the classic theory8 to explain these observations could be due to two of its assumptions: (i) age-specific genetic effects that necessarily lead to declining selection with age and (ii) absence of trade-offs between fecundity and survival across different ages. Reasoning within this scheme, our work shows that, once trade-offs are kept out of the picture and any sort of age-specific genetic effect is allowed, ageing remains the one and only stable outcome of evolution. We are then left with the dilemma of whether the observed lack of ageing in certain branches of the tree of life should be regarded as a merely transient phenomenon, as our stylized model would suggest, or whether trade-offs can stabilize the lack of ageing. We favour this second option for two main reasons. First, dependencies among fitness components have been shown pervasive in life history evolution41,42,43. Second, the application of optimization principles has already demonstrated how these can account for a vast array of different life histories14. In theoretical models, the specific functional form of trade-offs was already shown to determine whether ageing or something other than ageing is an evolutionarily stable strategy44,45,46,47,48. However, optimization models are not dynamic in that they do not describe how an ancestral population evolves over time. It would be interesting to apply a dynamical perspective to models that structure the life history into stages (e.g., size classes, phases of development)16. In stage-structured models, trade-offs between ages are deeply ingrained49, as a stage may lump together fecundity or survival over separate ages and could be under genetic control. These models, once equipped with dynamics, may give us a new perspective on the evolution of the trajectories of fecundity and survival over age23.
The classic theory was deemed “heuristic”50, presumably because of its lack of a dynamical dimension. Adding this dimension shows that attributing the evolution of ageing to a persistently declining force of selection with age is indeed a heuristic principle. But while insufficient to explain the various ways in which organisms are observed to allocate fecundity and survival in their lifespan, this principle is still valuable in giving us a glimpse into how ageing evolves. Violating the principle in fact does not affect the conclusion of the classic theory that when fecundity and survival evolve independently at each age, ageing is evolutionarily inevitable. However, the reasons behind this inevitability appear more subtle than originally thought and the observed lack of ageing in some species highlights the importance of trade-offs in life history evolution.
Methods
Detailed exposition and derivations are in the Supplementary Methods.
Demography, selection, and genetic effects
We consider a demographically stable population of constant, essentially infinite size where mj is average fecundity, i.e., number of offspring, at individual age j and pj is average survival, i.e., fraction surviving, from age j to age j + 1. Reproduction starts at age α and continues indefinitely. We define
-
ageing in fecundity as mj > mj+1 with j = α, α + 1, …
-
negative ageing in fecundity as mj < mj+1 with j = α, α + 1, …
-
ageing in survival as pj > pj+1 with j = α − 1, α, …
-
negative ageing in survival as pj < pj+1 with j = α − 1, α, …
The mean fitness in the population is
which can be seen as the reproductive value at birth in the demographically stationary state15,51,52. Mean fitness in the neutral population is 1. In this setting, the classic theory8 computes the selection force on age-specific fecundity and survival as proportional to the gradients
respectively, which are always positive, as fecundity and survival are direct fitness components. Supposing fecundity does not cease and survival is never perfect (<1) at any age,
which are the classic theory result8 of the steady decline of these gradients with age. Equation 2 presupposes that genetic effects are additive on fecundity, whence the identity function implicitly operating on mj on the left-hand side of eq. 2a, and proportional on survival, whence the natural logarithm operating on pj on the left-hand side of eq. 2b. To make this explicit, we introduce the functions fM and fP, which act on age-specific fecundity and on age-specific survival, respectively. We only assume these functions be strictly increasing, to preserve positive selection on fM(mj) and fP(pj), and twice differentiable. We use them to add appropriate weights to the classic selection gradients and get the general gradients,
which, as expected13, show no obvious age pattern. As an example of usage of these gradients, we recover the classic theory of additive effects on fecundity and proportional effects on survival when fM(mj) = mj and \({f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{P}}}}}}}}}({p}_{j})={{{{{{\mathrm{ln}}}}}}}\,{p}_{j}\). We can reverse the classic assumptions, as in Fig. 1, by setting \({f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}({m}_{j})={{{{{{\mathrm{ln}}}}}}}\,{m}_{j}\) and fP(pj) = pj. But the minimal assumptions about the f functions allow virtually any form of genetic effects, and not only additive and proportional, on fecundity and survival. For example, since \(-{{{{{{\mathrm{ln}}}}}}}\,{p}_{j}\) is average mortality between ages j and j + 1, when \({f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{P}}}}}}}}}({p}_{j})=-{{{{{{\mathrm{ln}}}}}}}\,(-{{{{{{\mathrm{ln}}}}}}}\,{p}_{j})\) we have proportional decrements in mortality. We emphasize that the f are not fitness functions. They only capture how age-specific genetic variation acts on fecundity and survival.
Model
To build our dynamical model, we use the breeder’s equation from quantitative genetics20,
which describes the time-discrete evolution of a mean trait (\({\bar{z}}_{j}\)) in a very large population under the action of selection when other traits (\({\bar{z}}_{i}\) with i ≠ j) are also under selection. In this equation, the change in a focal trait over one-time step is the sum of two terms. The first term is the product between the selection gradient \(\partial \bar{w}/\partial {\bar{z}}_{j}\) and the additive genetic variance gj for that trait. This term captures the role of the selection force alone on the trait, provided there is some variability for it (gj > 0). The second term, the sum in eq. (5), captures trade-offs between the focal trait and all other traits concomitantly subject to selection with gji the genetic covariance between traits i and j. In our usage of the breeder’s equation, we set covariances to zero so that trade-offs are absent. The additive genetic variance, the fuel of selection, is assumed very small, constant over time and equal for all traits, gj = δ with 0 < δ ≪ 1. Thus, all traits share and retain, the same potential to evolve and selection is weak. These assumptions are also implicit in the classical work by Hamilton8. We study fecundity evolution and survival evolution separately.
When we let fecundity evolve, survival at each age is kept a positive constant at all times but it may vary between ages. We set \({\bar{z}}_{j}={f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}({m}_{j})\) and use the selection gradient in eq. 4a inside the breeder’s equation. We then track change over time at the level of each mj via
where \({f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}^{-1}\) is the inverse function of fM and the quantity T is the average generation time, which is required to get the change per time step from the change \(\delta \frac{1}{f^{\prime}_{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}} ({m}_{j})}\frac{\partial \bar{w}}{\partial {m}_{j}}\) per generation. The factor ΩM(t) describes density dependence. We assume a constant population size regulated by ecological factors, which is achieved by scaling fecundity at all ages equally to ensure that \(\bar{w}(t)=\bar{w}(t+1)=1\), as suggested before53.
When we look at how survival evolves, we set \({\bar{z}}_{j}={f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{P}}}}}}}}}({p}_{j})\) and use the selection gradient in eq. 4b inside the breeder’s equation. Fecundities are set to positive constant parameters independent of one another. We then track change over time at the level of each pj via
Considerations analogous to eq. (6) apply.
As we presuppose potentially infinite ages, eqs. (6) and (7) give each rise to a separate dynamical system in the space of non-negative sequences of real numbers. The metric we use for this space is
with (an) and (bn) sequences and starting index i depending on the specific tail sequence of interest. The distance between (an) and a subset B of the space is \({d}_{i}(({a}_{n}),B)={\inf }_{({b}_{n})\in B}{d}_{i}(({a}_{n}),({b}_{n}))\).
Analysis of fecundity
We change coordinates for the system in eq. (6) to yj = mj+1/mj. With a first-order Taylor expansion around δ = 0, the transformed dynamics of fecundity are,
where the factor Mj remains positive at all times. Setting to zero the left-hand side of eq. (9) to get equilibria (denoted by asterisks), we find that, for ages j = α, α + 1, …,
From eqs. 2a and 4a we see in eq. (10) that the equilibrium selection gradient on fecundity declines with age when ageing in fecundity is an equilibrium. Independently of our choice of fM, there is no realistic equilibrium of the form \({m}_{j}^{* }={m}_{j+1}^{* }\) with j = α, α + 1, … , as this would lead to pj = 1 for j = α, α + 1, … implying the total absence of mortality during adulthood. Depending on the sign of \(\partial ({m}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}{({m}_{i})}^{2})/\partial {m}_{i}\), equilibrium fecundity, if it exists, shows ageing or negative ageing (Fig. 2). When \(\partial ({m}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}{({m}_{i})}^{2})/\partial {m}_{i} \, > \, 0\), ageing in fecundity is an equilibrium (\({y}_{j}^{* } \, < \, 1\) with j = α, α + 1, …). The distance between the evolving fecundity schedule (yn) = yα, yα+1, … and the set \({A}_{\,{ < }\,}^{m}\) of life histories with ageing in fecundity is
where Θ is the unit step function. This distance can be shown to decrease under eq. (9) when \(\partial ({m}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}{({m}_{i})}^{2})/\partial {m}_{i} \, > \, 0\). In particular, when \({f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}({m}_{i})={m}_{i}^{q}\) with q > 1/2,
is a Lyapunov function and when \({f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}({m}_{i})={a}_{1}\exp (c{m}_{i})/c+{a}_{2}\) with a1 > 0 and c > 0, any equilibrium can be shown linearly stable. When \(\partial ({m}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}{({m}_{i})}^{2})/\partial {m}_{i} \, < \, 0\), negative ageing in fecundity may be an equilibrium (\({m}_{j+1}^{* } \, > \, {m}_{j}^{* }\) with j = α, α + 1, …). Therefore, \({y}_{j}^{* } \, > \, 1\) with j = α, α + 1, … . The distance between (yn) and the set of \({A}_{ \,{ > }\,}^{m}\) of life histories with negative ageing in fecundity is
This distance can be shown to increase with time under eq. (9) when \(\partial ({m}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}{({m}_{i})}^{2})/\partial {m}_{i} \, < \, 0\) and (yn) is not in \({A}_{ \,{ > }\,}^{m}\). Moreover, keeping mα at equilibrium value and looking at the system in eq. (6) after a first-order Taylor expansion about δ = 0, it can be shown that the distance
between the subsequence \({({m}_{n})}_{\alpha +1}={m}_{\alpha +1},{m}_{\alpha +2},\ldots \,\) and its equilibrium, if this exists, increases with time when \(\partial ({m}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}{({m}_{i})}^{2})/\partial {m}_{i} \, < \, 0\). Irrespective of the sign of \(\partial ({m}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{M}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}{({m}_{i})}^{2})/\partial {m}_{i}\), it can be shown from eq. (10) that at most a single equilibrium with either ageing or negative ageing is possible—otherwise a contradiction with demographic stationarity is obtained.
Analysis of survival
We change coordinates for the system in eq. (7) to xj = pj+1/pj. With a first-order Taylor expansion around δ = 0, the transformed dynamics of survival are
where the factor Pj remains positive at all times. Setting the left-hand side of this expression to zero to calculate equilibria, we find that, for ages j = α − 1, α, …,
which, by eqs. 2b and 4b, implies that the equilibrium selection gradient always declines with reproductive age. Independently of our choice of fP, there is no equilibrium of the form \({p}_{j}^{* }={p}_{j+1}^{* } \, > \, 0\) with j = α − 1, α, …, as substituting this into eq. (16) and using eq. 2b we would get \({m}_{j}{p}_{0}^{* }{p}_{1}^{* }\ldots {p}_{j-1}^{* }=0\) for j = α, α + 1, …. The same problem derives from the assumption that fP is the natural logarithm. Since this is what the classic theory assumes, this theory fails to have an equilibrium in our model. Depending on the sign of \(\partial ({p}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{P}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}({p}_{i}))/\partial {p}_{i}\), equilibrium survival, if it exists, shows ageing or negative ageing (Fig. 3). When \(\partial ({p}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{P}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}({p}_{i}))/\partial {p}_{i} \, > \, 0\), only ageing in survival may be an equilibrium (\({x}_{j}^{* } \, < \, 1\) with j = α − 1, α, …). The distance between the evolving survival schedule \({({x}_{n})}_{\alpha -1}={x}_{\alpha -1},{x}_{\alpha },\ldots \,\) into reproductive ages and the set \({A}_{\,{ < }\,}^{p}\) of life histories with ageing in survival is
It can be shown that this distance tends to zero with time under eq. (15) when \(\partial ({p}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{P}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}({p}_{i}))/\partial {p}_{i} \, > \, 0\). When \(\partial ({p}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{P}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}({p}_{i}))/\partial {p}_{i} \, < \, 0\), negative ageing in survival may be an equilibrium (\({x}_{j}^{* } \, > \, 1\) with j = α − 1, α, …). The distance between the set \({A}_{ \,{ > }\,}^{p}\) of life histories with negative ageing in survival and an evolving survival schedule outside of this set is
This distance can be shown to increase with time under eq. (15) when \(\partial ({p}_{i}{f}_{{{{{{{{\rm{P}}}}}}}}}^{\prime}({p}_{i}))/\partial {p}_{i} \, < \, 0\).
Reporting summary
Further information on research design is available in the Nature Research Reporting Summary linked to this article.
Data availability
The authors declare that the data supporting the findings of this study are available within this paper and its supplementary information files.
References
Rose, M. R. Evolutionary Biology of Aging (Oxford Univ. Press, 1991).
Partridge, L. & Barton, N. H. On measuring the rate of ageing. Proc. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci. 263, 1365–1371 (1996).
Comfort, A. The Biology of Senescence (Elsevier, 1979).
Promislow, D. E. L. Senescence in natural populations of mammals: a comparative study. Evolution 45, 1869–1887 (1991).
Jones, O. R. et al. Diversity of ageing across the tree of life. Nature 505, 169–173 (2014).
Williams, G. C. Pleiotropy, natural selection, and the evolution of senescence. Evolution 11, 398–411 (1957).
Medawar, P. B. The Uniqueness of the Individual (Basic Books, 1958).
Hamilton, W. D. The moulding of senescence by natural selection. J. Theor. Biol. 12, 12–45 (1966).
Kirkwood, T. B. L. & Holliday, R. The evolution of ageing and longevity. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. B Biol. Sci. 205, 531–546 (1979).
Flatt, T. & Partridge, L. Horizons in the evolution of aging. BMC Biol. 16, 93 (2018).
Williams, G. C. & Taylor, P. D. In Evolution of Longevity in Animals (eds Woodhead, A. D. & Thompson, K. H.) Ch. 17 (Springer, 1987).
Williams, G. C. The Tithonus error in modern gerontology. Q. Rev. Biol. 74, 405–415 (1999).
Baudisch, A. Hamilton’s indicators of the force of selection. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 102, 8263–8268 (2005).
Baudisch, A. Inevitable Aging? Contributions to Evolutionary-Demographic Theory (Springer, 2008).
Charlesworth, B. Evolution in Age-Structured Populations 2nd edn (Cambridge Univ. Press, 1994).
Caswell, H. Matrix Population Models 2nd edn (Sinauer Associates, 2001).
Abrams, P. A. Does increased mortality favor the evolution of more rapid senescence? Evolution 47, 877–887 (1993).
Moorad, J. A., Promislow, D. E. L. & Silvertown, J. Evolutionary ecology of senescence and a reassessment of Williams’ ‘extrinsic mortality’ hypothesis. Trends Ecol. Evol. 34, 519–530 (2019).
Day, T. & Abrams, P. A. Density dependence, senescence, and Williams’ hypothesis. Trends Ecol. Evolution 35, 300–302 (2020).
Lande, R. In Evolution and Genetics of Life Histories (eds Dingle, H. & Hegmann, J. P.) Ch. 2 (Springer, 1982).
Partridge, L. & Barton, N. H. Optimality, mutation and the evolution of ageing. Nature 362, 305–311 (1993).
Abrams, P. A. The fitness costs of senescence: the evolutionary importance of events in early adult life. Evolut. Ecol. 5, 343–360 (1991).
Caswell, H. & Salguero-Gómez, R. Age, stage and senescence in plants. J. Ecol. 101, 585–595 (2013).
Wensink, M. Age-specificity and the evolution of senescence: a discussion. Biogerontology 14, 99–105 (2013).
Wachter, K. W., Evans, S. N. & Steinsaltz, D. The age-specific force of natural selection and biodemographic walls of death. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 110, 10141–10146 (2013).
Wachter, K. W., Steinsaltz, D. & Evans, S. N. Evolutionary shaping of demographic schedules. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 111, 10846–10853 (2014).
Promislow, D. E. L. & Tatar, M. Mutation and senescence: where genetics and demography meet. Genetica 102, 299–314 (1998).
Houle, D. et al. The effects of spontaneous mutation on quantitative traits. i. variances and covariances of life history traits. Genetics 138, 773–785 (1994).
Pletcher, S. D., Houle, D. & Curtsinger, J. W. Age-specific properties of spontaneous mutations affecting mortality in Drosophila melanogaster. Genetics 148, 287–303 (1998).
Leips, J., Gilligan, P. & Mackay, T. F. C. Quantitative trait loci with age-specific effects on fecundity in drosophila melanogaster. Genetics 172, 1595–1605 (2006).
Durham, M. F., Magwire, M. M., Stone, E. A. & Leips, J. Genome-wide analysis in drosophila reveals age-specific effects of SNPs on fitness traits. Nat. Commun. 5, 4338 (2014).
Hughes, B. G. & Hekimi, S. Different mechanisms of longevity in long-lived mouse and Caenorhabditis elegans mutants revealed by statistical analysis of mortality rates. Genetics 204, 905–920 (2016).
Flatt, T. & Schmidt, P. S. Integrating evolutionary and molecular genetics of aging. Biochim. Biophys. Acta 1790, 951–962 (2009).
Ackermann, M. & Pletcher, S. D. In Evolution in Health and Disease (eds Stearns, S. C. & Koella, J. C.) Ch. 18 (Oxford Univ. Press, 2007).
Williams, P. D., Day, T., Fletcher, Q. & Rowe, L. The shaping of senescence in the wild. Trends Ecol. Evol. 21, 458–463 (2006).
Charlesworth, B. Patterns of age-specific means and genetic variances of mortality rates predicted by the mutation-accumulation theory of ageing. J. Theor. Biol. 210, 47–65 (2001).
Vaupel, J. W. et al. Biodemographic trajectories of longevity. Science 280, 855–860 (1998).
Evans, S. N., Steinsaltz, D. & Wachter, K. W. A Mutation-Selection Model with Recombination for General Genotypes (American Mathematical Society, 2013).
Turelli, M. Phenotypic evolution, constant covariances, and the maintenance of additive variance. Evolution 42, 1342–1347 (1988).
Arnold, S. J. et al. Understanding the evolution and stability of the G-matrix. Evolution 62, 2451–2461 (2008).
Roff, D. A. Evolution of Life Histories: Theory and Analysis. (Chapman & Hall, 1992).
Stearns, S. C. The Evolution of Life Histories (Oxford Univ. Press, 1992).
Flatt, T. & Heyland, A. Mechanisms of Life History Evolution: The Genetics and Physiology of Life History Traits and Trade-offs (Oxford Univ. Press, 2011).
Kirkwood, T. B. L. & Rose, M. R. Evolution of senescence: late survival sacrificed for reproduction. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B: Biol. Sci. 332, 15–24 (1991).
Abrams, P. A. & Ludwig, D. Optimality theory, gompertz’ law, and the disposable soma theory of senescence. Evolution 49, 1055–1066 (1995).
McNamara, J. M. & Houston, A. I. State-dependent life histories. Nature 380, 215–221 (1996).
Vaupel, J. W., Baudisch, A., Dölling, M., Roach, D. A. & Gampe, J. The case for negative senescence. Theor. Popul. Biol. 65, 339–351 (2004).
Wensink, M. J., Wrycza, T. F. & Baudisch, A. No senescence despite declining selection pressure: Hamilton’s result in broader perspective. J. Theor. Biol. 347, 176–181 (2014).
Tuljapurkar, S. in Between Zeus and the Salmon: The Biodemography of Longevity (eds Wachter, K. W. & Finch, C. E.) Ch. 4 (National Academy Press, 1997).
Lande, R. A quantitative genetic theory of life history evolution. Ecology 63, 607–615 (1982).
Kozłowski, J. Measuring fitness in life-history studies. Trends Ecol. Evol. 8, 84–85 (1993).
Moorad, J. A. Individual fitness and phenotypic selection in age-structured populations with constant growth rates. Ecology 95, 1087–1095 (2014).
Mylius, S. D. & Diekmann, O. On evolutionarily stable life histories, optimization and the need to be specific about density dependence. Oikos 74, 218–224 (1995).
Acknowledgements
The authors thank Annette Baudisch for comments on an earlier draft and the Max Planck Society for funding.
Funding
Open Access funding enabled and organized by Projekt DEAL.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
S.G. conceived, developed, analyzed the model, and wrote a first draft of the manuscript. S.G. and A.T. reviewed the analysis and wrote the manuscript.
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Competing interests
The authors declare no competing interests
Peer review
Peer review information
Nature Communications thanks David Steinsaltz and the other, anonymous, reviewer(s) for their contribution to the peer review of this work. Peer reviewer reports are available.
Additional information
Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons license, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons license and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
About this article
Cite this article
Giaimo, S., Traulsen, A. The selection force weakens with age because ageing evolves and not vice versa. Nat Commun 13, 686 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-022-28254-3
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-022-28254-3
This article is cited by
-
Molecular mechanisms of aging and anti-aging strategies
Cell Communication and Signaling (2024)
-
Directional selection coupled with kin selection favors the establishment of senescence
BMC Biology (2023)
-
Targeting the “hallmarks of aging” to slow aging and treat age-related disease: fact or fiction?
Molecular Psychiatry (2023)
Comments
By submitting a comment you agree to abide by our Terms and Community Guidelines. If you find something abusive or that does not comply with our terms or guidelines please flag it as inappropriate.