This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution
Relevant articles
Open Access articles citing this article.
-
Defending an inclusive right to genital and bodily integrity for children
International Journal of Impotence Research Open Access 02 December 2021
Access options
Subscribe to this journal
Receive 8 print issues and online access
$259.00 per year
only $32.38 per issue
Rent or buy this article
Get just this article for as long as you need it
$39.95
Prices may be subject to local taxes which are calculated during checkout
Notes
The nuanced distinction between legal prohibition and criminalization, i.e. the decision to enforce a legal prohibition with criminal punishment, is eloquently explained by Merkel and Putzke [3].
The practice of (partially) removing the female foreskin or prepuce is also referred to as a ‘ritual nick’ (a small nick in the clitoral hood or vulva, which might not actually remove any tissue) or a clitoridotomy (removal of the clitoral hood—note this is not a clitoridectomy which affects the glans clitoris) and the latter is sometimes considered as the anatomical equivalent of male circumcision as commonly known in the West. The external clitoral glans and body (shaft) are not involved in these procedures and should, if performed by a sufficiently skilled practitioner, remain intact. This is the form of FGC that is most commonly practiced in South and Southeast Asia and is sometimes proposed as an alternative to more extensive procedures practiced elsewhere in the world as part of a harm-reduction strategy. In this context, two gynecologists have argued that particularly the ‘ritual nick’ should “not have a lasting effect on morphology or function” [1]. It is important to note that while a ritual nick can take place at a young age, it is anatomically difficult to perform a clitoridotomy in infancy and this usually takes place later in the child’s life. Male circumcision is generally performed in infancy by US Americans and Jews, while Muslims may perform the procedure anywhere from infancy to puberty. Circumcision could also be performed as a peripubertal rite of passage in Africa.
By using this terminology, I want to recognize that the child’s physical integrity is disrupted through a “cut,” without labeling the procedures as mutilation—which is a loaded term that precludes meaningful dialog and unnecessarily stigmatizes individuals, usually women, and minority communities. I do want to note, however, that the communities who value the practice of partial or total foreskin removal tend to refer to both male and female procedures as circumcision.
See for example Germany (2012), Iceland (2018) and Finland (2020) in Table 1.
See for example the proposal of the Tasmanian Law Reform Institute in Australia (2012) in Table 1.
Berer writes that, upon parental arrest, children are generally taken into the social care system, even when arrests are made based on suspicion or accusation alone, and forced to undergo (multiple) genital exams, see: [16]. For negative, and at time traumatic, effects of targeted genital exams see also: [17]. Further raising concerns is that expert witnesses might present significantly different interpretations of these exams because of limited knowledge and clinical experience with both FGC and the development of female genitalia, casting doubt as to whether parents are justly convicted. See for example: [18].
References
Arora KS, Jacobs AJ. Female genital alteration: a compromise solution. J Med Ethics. 2016;42:148–54.
Duivenbode R, Padela AI. The problem of female genital cutting: bridging Secular and Islamic bioethical perspectives. Perspect Biol Med. 2019;62:273–300.
Merkel, R., & Putzke, H. After Cologne: male circumcision and the law. Parental right, religious liberty or criminal assault? J Med Ethics. 2013;39:444–9.
Davis DS. Male and female genital alteration: a collision course with the law? Health Matrix. 2001;11:487–570.
The public policy advisory network on female genital surgeries in Africa. Seven things to know about female genital surgeries in Africa. Hastings Cent Rep. 2012;42:19–27.
Darby R. Moral hypocrisy or intellectual inconsistency?: A historical perspective on our habit of placing male and female genital cutting in separate ethical boxes. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 2016;26:155–63.
Earp BD. Between moral relativism and moral hypocrisy: reframing the debate on “FGM”. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 2016;26:105–44.
Duivenbode R, Padela AI. Female genital cutting (FGC) and the cultural boundaries of medical practice. Am J Bioeth. 2019;19:3–6.
Townsend KG. Defending the child’s right to bodily and genital integrity. IJIR.
American Academy of Pediatrics Task Force on Circumcision. Circumcision policy statement. Pediatrics. 2012;130:585–6.
Sorokan ST, FJC, JAL, CPSF and NC& ID and I Committee. Newborn male circumcision. Paediatrics Child Health. 2015;20:311–5.
Lægeforeningens politik vedrørende omskæring af drengebørn uden medicinsk indikation | læger.dk. https://www.laeger.dk/omskaering-af-drenge-uden-medicinsk-indikation-er-etisk-uacceptabelt
Shweder RA. Shouting at the Hebrews: imperial liberalism v liberal pluralism and the practice of male circumcision. Law Cult Humanit. 2009;5:247–65.
The Royal Dutch Medical Association (KNMG). Non-therapeutic circumcision of male minors. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: KNMG Viewpoint; 2010. p. 1–20.
Earp BD. Things I’ve learned (so far) about how to do practical ethics. Pract Ethics. 2014. http://blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk/2014/03/things-ive-learned-so-far-about-how-to-do-practical-ethics/
Berer M. The history and role of the criminal law in anti-FGM campaigns: Is the criminal law what is needed, at least in countries like Great Britain? Reprod Health Matters. 2015;23:145–57.
Johnsdotter, S. Meaning well while doing harm: compulsory genital examinations in Swedish African girls. Sex Reprod Health Matters. 2019;27:87–99.
Essén B. One Genital, Two Judgments: Why do “ expert witnesses” draw different conclusions in suspected cases of illegal cutting of girls’ genitals? In: Johnsdotter S, editor. Female genital cutting the global north and south. Centre for Sexology and Sexuality Studies. Sweden: Malmö; 2020. p. 259–88.
Jacobs AJ, Arora KS. Punishment of minor female genital ritual procedures: is the perfect the enemy of the good? Dev World Bioeth. 2017;17:134–40.
Jacobs AJ, Arora KS. Vulvar Nick and Metzitzah b’peh: punishment or harm reduction? In: Reproductive ethics. Cham: Springer; 2017. p. 151–69.
Isaiah Berlin (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/berlin/#EthiThouValuPlur
Galston WA. Liberal pluralism: the implications of value pluralism for political theory and practice. Cambridge University Press; 2002.
Jacobs AJ, Arora KS. When may government interfere with religious practices to protect the health and safety of children? Ethics Med Public Health. 2018;5:86–93.
Fateh-Moghadam B. Criminalizing male circumcision? Case note: Landgericht Cologne, Judgment of 7 May 2012 – No. 151 Ns 169/11. Ger Law J. 2012;13:1131–45.
Shweder RA, Much NC, Mahapatra M, Park L. The “big three” of morality (autonomy, community, divinity), and the “big three” explanations of suffering. In: Morality and heath. New York: Routledge; 1997.
Jacobs AJ. Is physical alteration a sufficient reason to prohibit ritual infant circumcision? J Relig Health. 2021.
Torcello L. Sophism and moral agnosticism, or, how to tell a relativist from a pluralist. Pluralist. 2011;6:87–108.
The Brussels Collaboration on Bodily Integrity. Medically unnecessary genital cutting and the rights of the child: moving toward consensus. Am J Bioeth. 2019;19:17–28.
Shweder RA. Equality now in genital reshaping: Brian earp’s search for moral consistency. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 2016;26:145–54.
Alahmad G, Dekkers W. Bodily integrity and male circumcision: an Islamic perspective. J Islamic Med Assoc N Am. 2012;44:1–9.
Sahih al-Bukhari, Vol. 7, Book 72, Hadith 779.
Savulescu J. Male circumcision and the enhancement debate: Harm reduction, not prohibition. J Med Ethics. 2013;39:416–7.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Prof. Shweder for many valuable conversations on genital cutting over the years, for his encouragement to take up this project, and for his expert advice while writing it. I would also like to acknowledge my colleagues Yaseen Andrewsen and Henry Brefka for their thorough feedback and support. The two anonymous reviewers and issue editors have helped me improve this text and I want to thank them warmly for their time and efforts.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Contributions
RD confirms sole responsibility for manuscript preparation.
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Competing interests
The author declares no competing interests.
Additional information
Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Duivenbode, R. Criminalizing medically unnecessary child genital cutting in Western countries: the terms of the debate and some reasons for caution. Int J Impot Res 35, 21–26 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41443-021-00491-y
Received:
Revised:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1038/s41443-021-00491-y
This article is cited by
-
Child genital cutting and surgery across cultures, sex, and gender. Part 1: female, male, intersex—and trans? The difficulty of drawing distinctions
International Journal of Impotence Research (2022)
-
Defending an inclusive right to genital and bodily integrity for children
International Journal of Impotence Research (2021)