Main

Correlations cry out for explanation1. Our intuitive understanding of correlations between events relies on the concept of causal influences, either relating directly the events, such as the position of the moon causing the tides, or involving a past common cause, such as seeing a flash and hearing the thunder when a lightning strikes. Importantly, we expect the chain of causal relations to satisfy a principle of continuity, that is, the idea that the physical carriers of causal influences propagate continuously through space at a finite speed. Given the theory of relativity, we expect moreover the speed of causal influences to be bounded by the speed of light. The correlations observed in certain quantum experiments call into question this viewpoint.

When measurements are performed on two entangled quantum particles separated far apart from each other, such as in an Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen5 type experiment, the measurement results of one particle are found to be correlated to that of the other particle. Bell showed that if these correlated values were due to past common causes, then they would necessarily satisfy a series of inequalities1. However, theory predicts and experiments confirm that these inequalities are violated2, thus excluding any past common cause type of explanation. Moreover, as the measurement events can be space-like separated6,7,8, any influence-type explanation must involve superluminal influences9, in contradiction with the intuitive notion of relativistic causality10.

This non-local connection between distant particles represents a source of tension between quantum theory and relativity10,11; however, it does not put the two theories in direct conflict owing to the no-signalling property of quantum correlations. This property guarantees that spatially separated observers in an Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen-type experiment cannot use their measurement choices and outcomes to communicate with one another. The complex relationship between quantum non-locality and relativity has been the subject of intense scrutiny9,10,11,12, but less attention has been paid to the fact that quantum non-locality seems to invalidate not only the intuitive notion of relativistic causality, but more fundamentally the idea that correlations can be explained by causal influences propagating continuously in space. Indeed, according to the standard textbook description, quantum correlations between distant particles, and hence the violation of Bell inequalities, can in principle be achieved instantaneously and independently of the spatial separation between the particles. Any explanation of quantum correlations using hypothetical influences would therefore require that they propagate at speed , that is jump instantaneously from one location to another as in real actions at a distance.

Is such an infinite speed a necessary ingredient to account for the correlations observed in nature or could a finite speed v, recovering a principle of continuity, be sufficient? In particular, could an underlying theory with a limit v on the speed of causal influences reproduce correctly the quantum predictions, at least when distant quantum systems are within the range of finite-speed causal influences13? Obviously, any such theory would cease to violate Bell inequalities beyond some range determined by the finite speed v. At first, this hypothesis seems untestable. Indeed, provided that v is large enough, any model based on finite-speed (hidden) influences can always be made compatible with all experimental results observed so far. It thus seems as if the best that one could hope for is to put lower bounds on v by testing the violation of Bell inequalities with systems that are further apart and better synchronized3,4.

Here we show that there is a fundamental reason why influences propagating at a finite speed v may not account for the non-locality of quantum theory: all such models give, for any v>c, predictions that can be used for faster-than-light communication. Importantly, our argument does not require the observation of non-local correlations between simultaneous or arbitrarily distant events and is thus amenable to experimental tests. Our results answer a long-standing question on the plausibility of finite-speed models first raised in refs 14, 15. Progress on this problem was recently made in ref. 16, where a conclusion with a similar flavour was obtained, but not for quantum theory. Technically, our approach is independent and different from the one in ref. 16, which relies on transitivity of non-locality, a concept that has not yet found any application in quantum theory.

We derive our results assuming that the speed of causal influences v is defined with respect to a privileged reference frame (or a particular foliation of spacetime into space-like hyperplanes). It should be stressed that although the assumption of a privileged frame is not in line with the spirit of relativity, there is also no empirical evidence implying its absence. In fact, even in a perfectly Lorentz-invariant theory, there can be natural preferred frames owing to the non-Lorentz-invariant distribution of matter—a well-known example of this is the reference frame in which the cosmic microwave background radiation seems to be isotropic (see, for example, ref. 17). Moreover, note that there do exist physical theories that assume a privileged reference frame and are compatible with all observed data, such as Bohmian mechanics18,19, the collapse theory of Ghirardi, Rimini and Weber20 and its relativistic generalization21. Although both of these theories reproduce all tested (non-relativistic) quantum predictions, they violate the principle of continuity mentioned above (otherwise they would not be compatible with no-signalling as our result implies).

The models that we consider, which we call v-causal models, associate with each spacetime point K a past and a future v-cone in the privileged frame, generalizing the notion of past and future light cones, see Fig. 1. An event at K1 can have a causal influence on a point K2>K1 located in its future v-cone and can be influenced by a point K3<K1 in its past v-cone. However, there cannot be any direct causal relation between two events K1K4 that are outside each other’s v-cones. The causal structure that we consider here thus corresponds to Bell’s notion of local causality9,22 but with the speed of light c replaced by the speed v>c. Operationally, it is useful to think of the correlations generated by v-causal models as those that can be obtained by classical observers using shared randomness together with communication at speed v>c.

Figure 1: Spacetime diagram in the privileged reference frame.
figure 1

In the (shaded) light cone delimited by solid lines, causal influences propagate up to the speed of light c, whereas in the v-cone (hatched region), causal influences travel up to the speed v. An event K1 can causally influence a space-like separated event K2 contained in its future v-cone and can be influenced by an event K3 that lies in its past v-cone, but it cannot directly influence or be influenced by event K4 outside its v-cone.

According to the textbook description of quantum theory, local measurements on composite systems prepared in a given quantum state ρ yield the same joint probabilities regardless of the spacetime ordering of the measurements. However, a v-causal model will generally not be able to reproduce these quantum correlations when the spacetime ordering does not allow influences to be exchanged between certain pairs of events. In particular, the correlations between A and B will never violate Bell inequalities when AB (see Fig. 2). A possible programme to rule out v-causal models thus consists of experimentally observing Bell violations between pairs of measurement events as simultaneous as possible in the privileged reference frame3. As pointed out earlier, however, this programme can at best lower bound the speed v of the causal influences.

Figure 2: Predictions of a v-causal model in a bipartite Bell experiment.
figure 2

We denote by P(a b|x y) the probability associated with A and B observing respectively the outcomes a and b when their measurement is labelled by x and y. In quantum theory, such probabilities are given by , where ρ is the quantum state of A and B and Max, Mby their respective measurement operators, and are independent of the spacetime ordering of the measurements. In contrast, in a v-causal model, the observed probabilities will depend on the spacetime ordering between A and B, as we now specify. a, A is in the past v-cone of B. Let the variable λ, with probability distribution q(λ), denote the joint state of the particles, or more generally a complete specification of any initial information in the shaded spacetime region that is relevant to make predictions about a and b (strictly, only the shaded region that is in the past v-cone of A can have a causal influence on A; however, all of our arguments still follow through even if we consider spacetime regions of the kind depicted). In this situation we can write , where we used Bayes’ rule in the second equality and the assumption that the measurement setting y is a free variable, that is, uncorrelated to a,x,λ, in the last equality. Note that there always exists a trivial v-causal model that reproduces the quantum correlations in the case A<B (or B<A) as we can write PQ(a b|x y) = PQ(a|x)PQ(b|y,a x) by the no-signalling property of quantum correlations (this easily generalizes to the multipartite case, see Supplementary Information SA). b, A and B are outside each other’s v-cones. As above, the variable λ represents a complete (as far as predictions about a and b are concerned) specification of the shaded spacetime region. Note that this region screens-off the intersection of the past v-cones of A and B, in the sense that given the specification of λ in the shaded region, specification of any other information in the past v-cones of A and B becomes redundant. It thus follows that P(a|x,b y λ) = P(a|x,λ) because any information about B is irrelevant to make predictions about a once λ is specified (see ref. 9 for a more detailed discussion of this condition). Similarly, P(b|y,a x λ) = P(b|y,λ). We can therefore write . Formally, the correlations are thus local and satisfy all Bell inequalities. In particular, the model cannot reproduce arbitrary quantum correlations in this situation.

More fundamentally, one could ask whether it is even possible to conceive a v-causal model that reproduces the quantum correlations in the favourable situation where all successive measurement events are causally related by v-speed signals, that is, when any given measured system can freely influence all subsequent ones? In the bipartite case, this is always possible (see Fig. 2 and Supplementary Information SA), and thus the only possibility is to lower bound v experimentally. In the four-partite case, however, we show below that any v-causal model of this sort necessarily leads to the possibility of superluminal communication, independently of the (finite) value of v. Importantly, the argument does not rely directly on the observation of non-local correlations between simultaneous events.

Let us stress that v-causal models evidently allow for superluminal influences at the hidden, microscopic level, provided that they occur at most at speed v. Such superluminal influences, however, need not a priori be manifested in the form of signalling at the macroscopic level, that is at the level of the experimenters who have no access to the underlying mechanism and hidden variables λ of the model, but can observe only the average probability P(a b|x y) (for example, by rotating polarizers along different directions x,y and counting detector clicks a,b). It is this later sort of superluminal communication that we show to be an intrinsic feature of any v-causal model reproducing quantum correlations.

A sufficient condition for correlations P not to be exploitable for superluminal communication is that they satisfy a series of mathematical constraints known as the no-signalling conditions. In the case of four parties (on which we will focus below), no-signalling is the condition that the marginal distributions for the joint system ABC are independent of the measurement performed on system D, that is,

together with the analogous conditions for systems ABD, ACD and BCD. Here P(a b c d|x y z w) is the probability that the four parties observe outcomes a,b,c and d when their respective measurements settings are x,y,z and w. These conditions imply that the marginal distribution for any subset of systems is independent of the measurements performed on the complementary subset.

Our main result is based on the following Lemma, whose proof can be found in Supplementary Information SB.

Lemma. Let P(a b c d|x y z w) be a joint probability distribution with a,b,c,d{0,1} and x,y,z,w{0,1} satisfying the following two conditions: first, the conditional bipartite correlations BC|AD are local, that is, the joint probabilities P(b c|y z,a x d w) for systems BC conditioned on the measurement settings and results of systems AD admit a decomposition of the form for every a,x,d,w; and second, P satisfies the no-signalling conditions (1). Then there exists a four-partite Bell expression S (see Supplementary Information SB for its description) such that correlations satisfying these two both conditions necessarily satisfy S≤7. On the other hand, there exist local measurements on a four-partite entangled quantum state that yield S7.2>7.

The Bell expression S has the extra property that it involves only the marginal correlations ABD and ACD, but does not contain correlation terms involving both B and C (this property is crucial for establishing our final result, as it implies that a violation of the Bell inequality can be verified without requiring the measurement on B and C to be simultaneous).

Consider now the prediction of a v-causal model in the thought experiment depicted in Fig. 3, where the spacetime ordering between the parties in the privileged frame is such that A<(BC). As B and C are outside each other’s v-cones, it follows immediately that the BC|AD correlations are local (see Supplementary Information SC for details). A violation of the Bell inequality S≤7 by the model in this configuration therefore implies that the second assumption of Lemma must be violated, that is that the correlations produced by the model violate the no-signalling conditions (1). It is easy to see that this further implies that these correlations can be exploited for superluminal communication (see caption of Fig. 3). It thus remains to be shown that the Bell inequality S≤7 is violated by a v-causal model in a configuration where BC, as standard quantum theory suggests. Note that this should not be taken for granted because one should not a priori expect a v-causal model to reproduce the quantum correlations in such a situation, for the same reason that in the bipartite case we do not expect a v-causal model to reproduce the quantum correlations when AB. Central to our argument lies the fact that the Bell expression S involves only the marginal correlations ABD and ACD, which allows one, as we show below, to infer its value in a situation where BC from observations in which B and C are not necessarily measured outside each other’s v-cones.

Figure 3: Four-partite Bell-type experiment characterized by the spacetime orderingcR = (A<(BC)).
figure 3

As B and C are both measured after A and D and satisfy BC, the BC|ADcorrelations produced by a v-causal model are local (see Supplementary Information SC). A violation of the inequality of Lemma by the model therefore implies that the corresponding correlations must violate the no-signalling conditions (1). At least one of the tripartite correlations ABC, ABD, ACD or BCD must then depend on the measurement setting of the remaining party. The marginal ABD (ACD) cannot depend on z (y), because this measurement setting is freely chosen at C (B), which is outside the past v-cone of A, B (C) and D (see also Supplementary Information SD). It thus follows that either the marginal ABC must depend on the measurement setting w of system D or that the marginal BCD must depend on the measurement setting x of system A (or both). Let the four systems lie along some spatial direction at, respectively, a distance dB = (1/4)(1+(1/r))+(1/(1+r)), dC = (3/4)(1+(1/r))−(1/(1+r)), dD = 1 from A, where r = v/c>1, and let them be measured at times tA = 0, tB = tC = 2/(c+v), tD = 1/v. Suppose that the BCD marginal correlations depend on the measurement x made on the first system A. If parties B and C broadcast (at light speed) their measurement results, it will be possible to evaluate the marginal correlations BCD, at the point D′. As this point lies outside the future light cone of A (shaded area), this scheme can be used for superluminal communication from A to D′. Similarly, if the ABC marginal correlations depend on the measurement w made on D, they can be used for superluminal communication from D to the point A′.

Explicitly, consider a modification of the thought experiment of Fig. 3, where the times tB and tC at which B and C are measured are chosen randomly so that any of the three configurations A∼C) can occur. Any v-causal model should at least reproduce the quantum correlations yielding S7.2>7 in the first two situations, in which finite speed influences can freely travel from the first measured party to the last one. In particular, the v-causal model thus reproduces the marginal quantum correlations ABD when A∼C). Operationally, this is very intuitive: in both cases BC and BSupplementary Information SD for a more detailed argument). Similarly, we can infer that the quantum ACD marginal obtained for A∼C. Together with the fact that the Bell expression S involves only the ABD and ACD marginals, a v-causal model must thus violate the inequality S≤7 in the configuration of Fig. 3, and hence give rise to correlations that can be exploited for superluminal communication.

In stark contrast with the bipartite scenario, these results therefore allow one to test experimentally the prediction of no-signalling v-causal models for any without requiring any simultaneous measurements. Indeed, the very same theoretical argument as that presented in the last paragraph can be used to deduce the value of S in the case BC by measuring the marginals ABD and ACD in situations in which B and C are not necessarily outside each other’s v-cones. For a more detailed discussion on some of the experimental possibilities that follow from our result, see Supplementary Information SE. Note that as with usual Bell experiments, depending on the assumption that one is willing to take, an experimental test of v-causal models may also need to overcome various loopholes. The way to remove these assumptions and overcome these loopholes is an interesting question that goes beyond the scope of our work but some possibilities are discussed in Supplementary Information SE.

We proved that if a v-causal model satisfies the requirement of reproducing the quantum correlations when the different systems are each within the range of causal influences of previously measured systems, then such a model will necessarily lead to superluminal signalling, for any finite value of v>c. Moreover, our result opens a whole new avenue of experimental possibilities for testing v-causal models. It also illustrates the difficulty to modify quantum physics while maintaining no-signalling. If we want to keep no-signalling, it shows that quantum non-locality must necessarily relate discontinuously parts of the universe that are arbitrarily distant. This gives further weight to the idea that quantum correlations somehow arise from outside spacetime, in the sense that no story in space and time can describe how they occur.